Index Robin Allott
THE MOTOR THEORY OF LANGUAGE: ORIGIN AND FUNCTION (Cortona 1988)
CONTENTS
1. THE THEORY
OUTLINED
2.
SUPPLEMENT AND EXTENSION
2.1 SUPPORT
2.2 SYNTAX
3. CONCLUSION
REFERENCES
1. THE THEORY OUTLINED
This paper presents the motor theory of language developed over the last few
years in earlier international conferences including particularly meetings of
the Language Origins Society. The theory is applied both to the origin of
language and to language as a current function. Part I gives a general outline
and Part II relates the theory to recent work in linguistics, brain research and
artificial intelligence.
There have been other motor theories of human function. In particular, there
was J.B. Watson's motor theory of thought and there was also the much-discussed
motor theory of speech perception. The theory presented here is a more general
one than either of these and it takes into account progress in research into the
organisation of action at the neural level. The theory is that language
originated as a transfer from or translation of the elements and system of
combination of elements of the neural motor system, with the expression of motor
programs which originally developed for the co-ordination of vertebrate movement
being redirected from the skeletal muscles to the muscles of the mouth, throat,
chest etc. with the side-product that this expression of the motor programs was
accompanied by the sound produced by modulated streams of air which we recognise
as speech-sound. The theory is thus one of a change in the connectability of the
neural system, the opening up of new channels for the external expression of
motor programs. "In the brain, new functions, phylogenetically and
ontogenetically, had to be grafted on to old ones in whatever manner proved to
be feasible and consistent with the normal processes of evolution. At every
stage, evolution had to improvise with the anatomical structures and inherent
plasticities that happened to be available"(Sommerhoff, 1974 p.13). In so far as
it is assumed that the redirection of the motor programs, the opening up of new
channels, took place many hundreds of thousands of years ago (and could in any
case never have been directly examined) the evidence for the motor theory cannot
be direct but must be probabilistic or circumstantial.
So much for a summary statement of the theory. But what do we mean by
language or by the origin of language? Language is taken to be the capacity of
one individual to alter, through structured sound emission, the mental
organisation of another individual. As regards the origin of language, we should
not look for a distinct, datable origin any more than we would look for a
distinct, datable origin for the eye. Language is more than speech just as
perception is more than the structure and functioning of the eye. In both cases
we have also to be concerned with the neural organisation underlying the
functions of speech and visual perception.
The implication of the proposition that language was constructed on the basis
of a previously existing complex system, the neural motor system, is that the
programs and procedures which evolved for the construction and execution of
simple and sequential motor movements formed the basis of the programs and
procedures going to form language. At every level of language, from the
elementary speech sounds, through the word-forms on to the syntactic rules and
structures, language was isomorphic with the neural systems which already
existed for the control of movement.
A second main idea is that language developed by a process of mosaic
evolution. This meant the fitting together of a whole array of elements,
anatomical, neural and behavioural. Many of the elements necessary for mosaic
evolution of the language capacity can be found in the anatomical and
behavioural repertoires of other animals, and particularly of birds.The
conclusion drawn is that if birds and other animals have, individually,
behavioural elements required for the evolution of human language-capacity, then
they must have the neural structures required to produce these behaviours, and
in particular the neural motor programs which are required to support
them.(Brown, 1974; Nottebohm, 1976; Phillips and Peck, 1975; Sutherland, 1964;
Thorpe, 1967; Welker, 1976). That other animals have these elements separately
also shows that a mechanism for the development or acquisition of the elements,
in evolutionary terms, must exist.
Whether or not the individual elements going to form the language capacity
each separately had survival-value -the development of language might have been
an example of evolution by accumulation of neutral mutations (Kimura, 1983) -
language as such clearly had a major survival value, not so much for the
individual as for the group which possessed language. Language is essentially
and unavoidably a group possession, a group behavioural attribute. As such, it
serves to increase a group's competitiveness and to promote evolution by way of
group-selection. Any group of animals with an effective means of communication
within the group e.g. ants or bees as well as humans, are in a position to react
to events external to the group with a group-reaction, and so also to be subject
to evolution by way of group-selection rather than individual selection. Hence
the evolution of diverse castes of ants, bees and termites. In the case of
humans, "it seems necessary to invoke a selective process acting between group
and group, with the groups persisting as semi-permanent units, giving time for
the better-integrated ones to prosper and supplant those that are less vigorous"
applying Wynne Edwards' comment (1986 p.1) to the usefulness of language to
competing human groups. Eibl-Eibesfeldt refers in this connection to Bigelow's
view that the origin of man's rapid evolution lies in inter-group warfare...
"man's tendency to cluster into small groups (pseudospeciation) and to compete
aggressively with others certainly provided a motive force for this evolutionary
development. In a tragic way we are indebted to aggression for the rapid
development of our intellect" (Eibl-Eibesfeldt, 1975 p.509)- one of the most
powerful forces in pseudospeciation and in aggressive intergroup struggle must
have been the development of language.
Mosaic elements required for language notably include imitation and the
categorical perception of speech sound. We take the power of imitation in
ourselves, in birds such as the parrot or mynah, and in animals such as the
chimpanzee, very much for granted but imitation, of speech or other sound or
bodily movement, is in reality a most surprising ability. It involves a
remarkable and complex linking of perception and motor organisation. The ability
of some birds, mynah birds par excellence (Thorpe, 1967), to imitate human
speech sounds precisely shows that the production of the sounds of speech is not
dependent on any narrowly specified articulatory apparatus, and suggests that
one should not expect to trace the development of speech simply in terms of
gross anatomical features (Nottebohm, 1976; Wind, 1976). A second important
mosaic element for language is the capacity to discriminate categorically
between human speech sounds in a way similar to that found in adult speech
perception - an ability found in a variety of animals, notably in chinchillas
(Burdick and Miller, 1975; Kuhl and Miller, 1975), monkeys - and indeed in
extremely young human infants.(Morse, 1976; Kuhl, 1987; Kuhl and Meltzoff, 1982)
A crucial feature in each of these two important elements of the mosaic, and
in other behavioural requirements for language, is the intimate involvement of
the motor control system and their dependence on cross-modal processes. The
development of the language capacity has resulted from the progressive
establishment of new cross-modal(Ettlinger, 1967; Ettlinger and Blakemore, 1967)
or trans-functional neural linkages, cerebral re-organisation in the sense that
the interconnectedness of different brain regions concerned with what are
usually considered distinct functions, has substantially increased. Evolution of
language brought together in the human brain homologues or analogues of neural
structures spread across a range of animals, and established neural connections
between them.
Such an extensive relation between language and the motor system is what one
might reasonably expect, given the central role of the motor system in all
behaviour and the essentially motor character of speech production, as the
outcome of movements of the articulatory apparatus.(Fowler et al., 1980; Kertesz
and Hooper, 1982; Kimura, 1973, 1976; McNeill, 1981; Ojemann and Mateer, 1979;
Penfield and Roberts, 1959) The existence of a relation with the motor system
has long been recognised, for example in the speech perception theory associated
with the Haskins Laboratories and Alvin Liberman.(Liberman et al., 1967;
Liberman and Mattingly, 1985) In view of the prominence of the motor system in
the mosaic elements which might have gone to form the language-capacity, it
seems a necessary next step to undertake a systematic examination of what is
known about the relation between each aspect of language and corresponding
features of motor activity and the motor system. In addition, because of the
intimate relation between the use and content of language on the one hand and
perception on the other, the examination should extend to the relation between
the motor system and perception in all its forms.(Turvey, 1977) The motor system
is seen as the indispensable mediator between different modalities, and
particularly between language and perception.
This leads on to the idea that the neural motor system may be formed from a
limited array of components. In an earlier paper (at Cracow in 1986) I suggested
that new light could be thrown on this by using the hypothesis that the motor
system, prior to the development of language, was built up from a limited number
of primitive elements - units of motor action - which could be formed into more
extended motor programs.This would make it possible to look for a direct
correspondence between the primitive motor elements and the fundamental elements
of spoken language, the phonemic system, and at the same time would allow one to
derive the processes of word-formation and syntactic rules for constructing
word-sequences from the neural rules governing the union of motor elements into
simple and more complex actions. Motor activity and speech activity would thus
be shown to have similar and in fact systematically related structures and
rules. Language would be one type, though an exceptionally special and valuable
type, of skilled action.
It followed from this that one must deal with the system of motor control and
the nature of motor programming.(Bernstein, 1967; Brooks, 1986; Evarts et al.,
1985; Hoyle, 1983; Kelso & Clark, 1982; Schmidt, 1982) The effect of linking
the system of motor control for bodily movement to the neural control of the
mouth and other anatomical elements which became part of the articulatory
system, was that new channels were opened up for the external expression of
motor programs The motor system already has externally expressive functions,
most notably in facial expression. If language is derived from the motor system,
one preliminary but important point is that language cannot be in any way
arbitrary. This applies not only to the sound-elements of language, the phonemic
system, but also to the words formed from these elements and to the ordering
rules which constitute the syntactic structure of language. There is strong
experimental evidence that the phonemic system is not arbitrary (Kuhl, 1987;
Lindblom, 1983; Macneilage, 1983), suggestive evidence that word-forms are not
arbitrary but are expressive or appropriate to their meaning (Allott, 1973;
Brown, 1958; Koehler, 1964) and there is also considerable evidence for a
fundamental relation between the syntax of language and physiological syntax,
the syntaxes of action and perception.(Kertesz and Hooper, 1982; Kimura, 1973;
Lashley, 1951; Lieberman, 1984; McNeill, 1981; Ojemann & Mateer, 1979) There
is no evidence which compels one to accept that phonemes, words or syntax are
arbitrary. This conclusion, that language is not arbitrary, in phonology, syntax
or lexicon, runs counter to accepted linguistic orthodoxy. It provokes the
immediate challenge how then can one explain the extent of diversity between
languages, particularly in lexicon. The topic is important enough to justify
full-length treatment and has been dealt with in my paper for the 1989 LOS
Meeting at the University of Texas, Austin, under the title 'Reconciling the
Motor Theory and the Diversity of Languages'
An unexpected result of this approach was the perception that the motor
theory is not only a theory of language origin and development but also a theory
of current language function. The proposition that language is completely
analogous to skilled motor action opens up a new direction of enquiry, the
applicability to language of the extensive and surprisingly successful research
into the neural bases of action, of motor control. Recent research (Bizzi, 1983;
Desmedt, 1985; Evarts et al., 1985; Hollerbach, 1985; Kelso & Clark, 1982;
McKay, 1985; Marsden et al., 1985; Robertson & Pearson, 1985; Selverston,
1985; Taub et al., 1973) strongly supports the concept of motor programs and
motor subprograms as real and not merely formal or theoretical bases for the
organisation of action. An important task in brain theory is to isolate the
substructures of motor behaviour, to identify what might be called the
repertoire of detached motor programs and sub-programs, and how these are used
by central organising programs. The elementary motor programs may well be
innate, part of standard human (and even vertebrate) neural structure. They may
form part of fixed action programs or be formed by a central motor program into
novel action-sequences. Motor programs are not necessarily dependent for their
functioning upon incoming sensory information. They may run without any afferent
information, as research on invertebrates has shown. The similarities in motor
programming between a wide range of animals, birds, insects, suggest that common
general principles have evolved in neural control of movement. In humans, in the
light of evidence bearing directly on the relation between arm and head
movements and speech, one may reasonably look for parallel pre-programming of
the comparable speech musculature movements.
It is possible to examine the implications of the proposed relation between
motor programming and speech programming at each level, the phonemic, the
lexical and the syntactic. For phonemes, this leads to the idea of an invariant
program for each phoneme, or 'auditory targetting' (Lindblom, 1983; Macneilage,
1983), a motor-alphabet underlying speech, related in some way to the elementary
motor-patterns underlying other forms of action.The surprising phenomenon of
categorical speech perception has a direct bearing on this. A range of animals
and very young infants have displayed, in repeated experiments, the ability to
categorise speech-sounds, natural or synthesised, in ways which match the
category boundaries in adult speech; very young infants have been shown to
discriminate categorically speech-sounds not found in their mother
language.(Kuhl, 1987) On the motor theory presented in this paper, the
explanation for this must be that the categorisation of speech-sounds is derived
from organisation prior to language, and specifically from the categorisation of
motor programs used in constructing and executing all forms of bodily action.
What the rhesus monkey, or the chinchilla, share with the young human infant is
very similar skeletal and muscular organisation, with very similar processes for
the neural control of movement generally.The specificity of the phoneme is the
accidental result of the application of the different elementary motor
subprograms to the muscles which went to the form the articulatory system.The
hierarchical structure of the motor system is built on the basis of a limited
set of motor elements, which are combined in an unlimited number of ways
(motor-words), just as phonemes can form an unlimited number of spoken words.
Words, as neural structures, can be formed from the co-activation of the
motor subprograms for phonemes which are then melded or shingled together to
form a distinct neural program for the whole word. Words are a read-out of
neural structures in much the same way as actions or facial expressions.
Experimental approaches with the creation of artificial words have suggested
that there can be a lawful relation between speech-sounds and auditory or visual
percepts. Research into sound-symbolism strongly suggests that there is an
isomorphism at the motor level between speech and the contents of perception.
The object seen produces a motor-pattern which is readily transferable as a
motor-program to the articulatory system and so becomes the associated word for
the thing. The process involved is similar to that by which we transfer into our
own neural organisation the motor-program underlying the facial expression of
others, smiling, yawning or frowning, and so may reproduce in our own expression
the expression which we perceive in another.
The motor programs which go to form the neuromuscular sequences underlying
words are derived from the integration of the neural structures underlying
perception in all its forms (visual, auditory, tactile etc.) and motor
organisation. The assumption that the last stage of the perceptual process and
the first stage of the motor process are one and the same is attractive because
it solves the problem of imitation. The subparts of the perception and action
systems are thought of as pieces of a jigsaw puzzle that are made to fit each
other.(Turvey, 1977)
If phonemes and word-forms are derived ultimately from the motor system (if
necessary modulated by the perceptual system) it seems inevitable that there
must also be a close relation between the organisation of motor activity, motor
syntax, and the organisation of language, speech syntax. If this is so, then
beside speech-elements (phonemes), speech-element compounds (words) and speech
sequences (syntax word-strings) on this theory one can now set a motor-alphabet
(of elementary motor programs for bodily action), an array of motor-words
(actions formed from motor-elements) and motor-sentences (formed from sequences
of motor-words). Section B of Part II of this paper briefly discusses more
detailed aspects of the relation between the motor theory and syntax.
As already indicated, the motor theory of the origin and development of
language in this paper is also in substance a motor theory of the current
functioning of language. A theory of this kind fits well with the current trend
of research into neural motor control and the neural basis of perception. It
also has points in common with what Pribram described as his central motor
theory of the origins of human language, based on a close relation between the
imaging of action, perception and speech(Pribram, 1971 p.369). It is built
fairly directly on Karl Lashley's (1951) ideas on the underlying uniformity of
the neural organisation of action and language, though it inverts his approach;
where he started from the then current analysis of the hierarchical structure of
language, the present approach takes motor programming as primary and derives
the structure of language, as a motor phenomenon, from the necessary processes
in the organisation of action, as demonstrated in research into neural control
of behaviour patterns in a range of experimental animals. Curiously, this theory
could be presented as a return, at a deeper level, to earlier ideas on the
essentially motor basis of brain processes, though Watson of course had an
over-simplified and incorrect view of the real complexities involved in motor
organisation. Because the motor theory of the origin and development of language
is at the same time a theory of the current functioning of language, it is also
potentially a theory of the ontogenetic as well as phylogenetic development of
language. It can be a useful instrument for illuminating and investigating both
speech and motor organisation, at the neural level and in extended speech and
action sequences.
2. SUPPLEMENT AND EXTENSION
Section 2.1 presents material drawn from a variety of specialist fields
tending to support the importance of the relation between motor control and
language. The growing consensus unfortunately still excludes linguists wedded to
a generative or purely formal approaches to language function. Section 2.2
summarises an approach to the application of the motor theory to syntax
(discussed more fully in a paper on syntactic iconicity presented at the 12th
International Congress of Anthropological and Ethnological Sciences).
2.1 SUPPORT FOR THE MOTOR THEORY
Over the last few years there has been a good deal of research and
theoretical development which directly or indirectly supports the central idea
of the motor theory, that language is founded on the pre-existing structures of
the motor control system of the brain. The material comes from a number of
directions, neurology, artificial intelligence and computer modelling of brain
function, linguistics, language pathology.
In mainstream philosophy, Patricia Churchland (1986) has sought to bring home
to philosophers the relevance and importance of progress in brain research. This
leads her to recognise the importance of motor organisation: "If we think of
motor control as a fundamental function for nervous systems, then increased
sophistication in nervous systems is, in this broad sense, understandable as an
increasingly sensitive means of controlling behavior on the basis of sensory
information. As organisms compete for scarce resources, efficiency of motor
control is at a premium; and nervous systems with more sophisticated motor
control will have a selective advantage over those whose motor control is less
efficient... To follow evolution's footsteps in discovering how basic principles
of motor control are refined and upgraded to yield more complex systems is a
productive strategy. Additionally, it may be a shift in focus that allows us a
breakthrough in the attempt to understand the higher functions. If we can see
how the complexity of behavior that we call cognition evolved from solutions to
basic problems in sensorimotor control, this can provide the framework for
determining the nature and dynamics of cognition... Put crudely brains are not
in the business of pattern recognition for its own sake, and the nature of
pattern recognition, as accomplished by brains, must be understood in the
context of its role in how brains achieve motor control. Evolution being what it
is, pattern recognition is there to subserve motor coordination. And what goes
for pattern recognition in this regard goes also for learning and memory... if
we ignore motor control as the context within which we try to understand pattern
recognition, we run the risk of generating biologically irrelevant
solutions."(p. 441, p. 473)
In the AI approach to language, Arbib and his collaborators have aimed at
approaches which are plausible in terms of neurology. Most practitioners of
cognitive science "believe that their ignorance of brain research is a virtue,
and that human intelligence can be studied as symbol-manipulation without
concern for its embodiment... [Arbib's latest book Arbib et al., 1987] offers a
view of cognitive science that places linguistics in a common framework, offered
by schema theory, with research in brain theory and the study of action and
perception.. To provide a bridge to our analysis of perception, we now observe
that there are important parallels between visual perception and speech
understanding on the one hand, and between speech production and motor control
on the other... While noting that language behavior is highly developed in
humans, we stress that it is a system of communication and that it involves both
action and perception. We see it as mediated by a brain that has evolved from
other brains, and thus, as one of several goals, we seek to understand the brain
mechanisms of language within a wider analysis of brain mechanisms subserving
action and perception". Arbib suggests "that language did not arrive de novo but
came by differentiation of, and building upon, pre-existing systems (such as the
perceptual-motor systems..)".(pp. v, 5, 15, 68)
From linguistics, Jackendoff in a recent paper: "How can we talk about what
we see?.. one of the most fundamental problems for a theory of natural
language.. A point of connection must be found between the theory of language
and the theory of vision".(Jackendoff, 1987 p.90) Slobin summing up an extremely
extensive cross-linguistic survey of language acquisition concludes: "Detailed
examination of the ways in which children acquire a variety of different types
of languages leads to the inescapable conclusion that the structure of human
language is highly adapted to the structure of human perception, thought and
action - and that the capacity to construct a human language must, ultimately,
be part of the genetic capacity of our species".(Slobin, 1985 p. 1244)
From clinical brain research (direct electrical stimulation of the exposed
cortex as part of the treatment of epilepsy), Ojemann: "These observations also
suggest the conclusion that a large portion of the brain related to language is
fundamentally a part of the motor system. Other evidence for the concept has..
been presented by Kimura and her associates".(Ojemann, 1983 p. 195) Buckingham
in commenting on Ojemann's important 1983 article: "The commonalities with
language production and other motor functions lead to the ultimate claim that
the linguistic system has been evolutionarily built upon the general motor
capacities of the brain".(Buckingham, 1983 p. 209)
Studdert-Kennedy (referring to Ojemann's findings):"Taken together, these
facts almost force the hypothesis that the primary specialisation of the left
hemisphere is motoric rather than perceptual. Language would then be drawn to
the left hemisphere because the left hemisphere already possessed the neural
circuitry for control of the fingers, wrists and arms..- precisely the type of
circuitry needed for control of the larynx, tongue, velum, lips and of the
bilaterally innervated vocal apparatus".(Studdert-Kennedy, 1982 p. 333)
There has been a good deal of use of the concept of persisting motor programs
that can be assembled into large structures or applied to different
muscle-groupings. Apart from the general evolutionary and functional link
between motor control and language, an important aspect of the theory is the
idea that both motor programs and language are formed from elementary units,
with units of motor action being directly related to units of speech-sound. In a
recent paper, Soviet researchers suggest:"It is likely that the most complex
motor acts, such as speech production, are based on the ability of the nervous
system to combine different motor components. Comparison of central mechanisms
for speech production and for limb movements is a special theme that is now very
much under discussion." Discussing adaptability of innate motor patterns and
motor control mechanisms: "Adaptability of movements is based on their discrete
organisation.. it is common to find that movement trajectories are divisible
into segments with various parameters (curvature, speed etc.) This segmentation
may also indicate that movements are a combination of elementary dynamic
components". Referring to multiple forms of motor-equivalent programs: "The
motor programs considered.. remain unchanged in form during continuous
regulation of the parameters involved".(Berkinblit, Feldman and Fukson, 1986 pp.
594-598) Similarly, Gracco and Abbs : "these results and discussion point to a
dynamic hierarchical model of speech motor control utilising distributed motor
control processes and interacting neural subsystems... This flexible
hierarchical system allows for the operation of multiple, parallel, subtask
actions.. Together these distributed sensorymotor systems appear to interact
dynamically to produce the coordinated movements of human speech."(Gracco and
Abbs, 1987 p. 191)
2.2 SYNTAX AND THE MOTOR THEORY
This section summarises some still tentative ideas on the more detailed
relation of the motor theory of language to syntax (in the context of discussion
of the iconicity of syntax). Iconicity is interpreted essentially as mapping or
isomorphism from one structure to another, eg. from visual or action
organisation to syntax. But there is no consensus about the concept of syntax. I
take it to be the processes by which words are put together to convey meaning,
not accepting the currently fashionable view that syntax is to be defined as the
formulation of rules to generate acceptable, ie grammatically well-formed,
sentences in any language. This undervalues the importance of meaning in
language as contrasted with grammatical form.
There are three major components of any syntax (on the interpretation of
syntax I am using). The first component comprises the principal word categories
Noun and Verb to which should added the dependent categories of Adjective and
Adverb; the second component comprises ordering and sub-ordering rules for
word-strings; the third component consists of the closed class of function words
(and function sub-words, functional morphemes). The syntax of a language results
from the co-operation and interaction of the three major components.
What justification is there for choosing these three major components? Little
needs to be said about the justification for selecting the principal word
categories as a major component of syntax or for treating ordering (and
sub-ordering) rules as a major component - there is general acceptance of these
in all current discussion of syntax. More extended justification is needed for
treating the class of function words as a distinct major component of syntax;
evidence for the neurological, and operational reality of the closed class is
drawn from clinical findings in aphasia, from brain stimulation experiments in
the treatment of epilepsy and from the use of function words as a key component
in AI natural language parsing programs.
Using this identification of the major components in syntax, the next step is
to explore the significance of the motor theory in relation to each of the major
components, that is, the detailed possible relation between motor control (both
for bodily action and for vision) and the principal open word-categories,
word-order and the class of function words.
For the open categories (Nouns and Verbs), the existence of these classes is
seen as deriving both from the actual manner of operation of vision - the
pattern of movements of the eye (saccades, fixations, tremor and accommodation).
These aspects of the motor functioning of the eye already show a clear
distinction between visual operations relating to static elements in the visual
scene and visual operations involving perception of movement and change in the
visual scene. Once the broad parallel between Nouns and Verbs and static and
movement aspects of visual perception is established, the two dependent classes
follow (Adjectives and Adverbs) as modifiers of the leading categories.
For the second major component of syntax (ordering and sub-ordering of words
in the utterance) the relation postulated is between the word-string as a serial
process and the action of visual perception also as a serial process governed by
the pattern of scanning over the visual scene (including aspects of salience and
emphasis). At the same time, ordering of the word-string is linked to the serial
ordering of bodily action more generally, where salience may be equated with
variations in relative force of different segments of a complex action.
The relation of the motor theory to the third major component of syntax, the
closed class of function words, is in some ways the most important, and at the
same time requires the breaking of the most new ground. The function word
component of syntax is where the most considerable differences are observed
between languages in terms of how far they depend on separate function words, as
largely in English, and how far they depend on function sub-words (inflections,
morphemes for forming eg. abstract word-classes etc).
To relate the class of function-words to the motor theory, the first step is
to prepare a list of words considered to be function words. This cannot be based
on any simple treatment of traditional parts of speech, prepositions,
conjunctions etc. as function words. A function word or function subword is a
speech-form which has no definable external reference and which acts in
association with other function words to determine the role of non-function
words in the word string or utterance (in English often to decide whether
open-class words are acting as Nouns, Verbs or Adjectives and whether the
non-function words are operating as Subject, Object, Complement etc).
If, as the theory proposes, the syntactic components are derived from the
motor control system (either from the organisation of action or from the motor
control organisation underlying perception), then the next stage is to consider
how in detail the closed-class of function words and subwords have analogues in
the motor control system or could be derived from aspects of motor programming
required for what Gregory described as 'the grammar of vision' or from what a
motor control researcher referred to as 'the grammar of action'.
Features of function words which can be compared with operational aspects of
'action grammar' or 'vision grammar' include, for example, timing, direction and
relative position, salience, emphasis and force, hesitation, choice, change of
direction, linkage and sequence.
Classification of function words using categories such as these is meant only
as an indication of the lines along which study of the relation between motor
programming and the class of function words might proceed. What it might lead to
is a clearer idea of how the segments of motor programs might be fitted
together, using our knowledge of syntax (in the sense proposed in this paper) to
throw light on motor control just as much as using motor control and vision
research to help us to tackle syntax in a new and biologically more relevant
way.
3. CONCLUSION
This paper has covered a good deal of ground and in particular has dealt with
material on motor control less familiar to readers concerned primarily with
language. It is inevitable that a theory of language origin which relates the
structures of language to the (previously evolved) vertebrate neural structures
for movement should attempt to demonstrate a secure basis in current research
into motor control. Neural motor control is a vast and active field of research;
some attempt was made in earlier papers for LOS meetings, at Oxford in 1986 and
at Vanderbilt in 1987, to draw together the relevant results and theories. The
main points relevant for the motor theory are:
1. The central role in all behaviour of motor control. Language is an
important segment of behaviour; it is itself action and is integrated with
perception and bodily action.
2. Motor control makes use of modules, pre-wired motor programs. Thus there
are elements (motor units) which can be put in correspondence with the
sound-elements of language. There must also be neural rules for forming motor
programs into action-sequences; these served as the basis for the syntactic
rules by which words are assembled into utterances.
3. An important issue in motor control research is the operational links
between perception and action. The motor theory of language origin proposes that
the original structures of word-forms were derived from the neural processes
linking perception and action.
- Allott RM: The Physical Foundation of Language. Seaford: ELB, 1973.
- Arbib MA, EJ Conklin and JC Hill: From Schema Theory to Language. New
York: Oxford University Press, 1987.
- Berkinblit MB, AG Feldman and OI Fukson: Adaptability of innate motor
patterns and motor control mechanisms. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9:
585-63, 1986.
- Bernstein N: The Co-ordination and Regulation of Movements. Oxford:
Pergamon, 1967.
- Bizzi E: Central processes involved in arm movement control. In The
production of speech. ed. P, Macneilage, pp. 3-10. New York: Springer-Verlag,
1983.
- Bower TG: The object in the world of the infant. Scientific American 225:
30-38, 1971.
- Brooks VB: The neural basis of motor control. London: Oxford University
Press, 1986.
- Brown JL: Brain stimulation parameters affecting vocalisation in birds. In
Birds, Brain and Behaviour. ed. by I.J. Goodman and M.W.Schein, pp. 87-99.
London: Academic Press, 1974.
- Brown R: Words and Things. New York: The Free Press, 1958.
- Buckingham HW: Peer Commentary on Ojemann. Behavioral and Brain Sciences
209, 1983.
- Burdick CK and JB Miller: Speech perception by the chinchilla. Journal of
the Acoustic Society of America. 58: 415-427, 1975.
- Butterworth B (ed): Explanations for language universals. Berlin: Mouton,
1984.
- Churchland P: Neurophilosophy: Towards a Unified Science of the
Mind-Brain. Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T Press, 1986.
- de Diego VG: Lecciones de Linguistica Espa÷ola. Madrid: Editorial Gredos,
1973.
- Desmedt JE: Patterns of commands during various types of voluntary
movement in man. In The motor system in neurobiology ed by EV Evarts, SP Wise
and D Bousfield, pp. 133-139 Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1985.
- Eibl-Eibesfeldt I: Ethology: The biology of behavior. New York: Holt,
Rinehart and Winston, 1975.
- Ettlinger G: Analysis of cross-modal effects and their relationship to
language. In Brain Mechanisms underlying Speech and Language. ed by CG
Millikan and FL Darley, pp. 53-60. New York: Grune and Stratton, 1967.
- Ettlinger G and CB Blakemore: Cross-modal matching in the monkey.
Neuropsychologia 5: 147-154, 1967.
- Evarts EV, SP Wise and D Bousfield: The motor system in Neurobiology.
Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1985.
- Fowler CA, P Rubin, RE Remez and MT Turvey: Implications for speech
production of a general theory of action. In Language Production Vol. I:
Speech and talk. ed by B Butterworth, pp. 373-420. London: Academic Press,
1980.
- Gallistel CR: The organisation of action: A new synthesis. Hillsdale,
N.J.: Erlbaum Associates, 1980.
- Gracco VL and JH Abbs: Programming and Executive Processes of Speech
Movement Control: Potential Neural Correlates. In Motor and Sensory Processes
of Language ed by E Keller and M Gopnik, pp. 163-201. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum
Associates., 1987.
- Granit R: The Purposive Brain. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1977.
- Hollerbach JM: Computers, brains and the control of movement. In The motor
system in neurobiology ed by EV Evarts, SP Wise & D Bousfield, pp.
140-146. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1985.
- Hoyle G: Muscles and their neural control. New York: John Wiley., 1983.
- Humboldt W von: Linguistic variability and intellectual development Vol. 1
of Uber die Kawisprache auf der insel Java 1836 Trans. by GC Buck and FA
Raven. Coral Gables, Florida: University of Miami Press, 1971.
- Huxley A: Reflections on Muscle. Sherrington Lecture. Liverpool: Liverpool
University Press, 1980.
- Jackendoff R: On Beyond Zebra: The relation of linguistic and visual
information. Cognition 26: 89-114., 1987.
- Kelso JAS and JE Clark eds: The development of movement control and
coordination. New York: Wiley, 1982.
- Kertesz A and P Hooper: Praxis and language. Neuropsychologia. 20:
275-286, 1982.
- Kimura D: Manual activity during speaking. Neuropsychologia 11: 45-55,
1973.
- Kimura D: The neural basis of language qua gesture. In Studies in
Neurolinguistics. ed H Whitaker, pp. 145-156. New York: Academic Press, 1976.
- Kimura M: The Neutral Theory of Molecular Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1983.
- Kohler W: Psychologie de la forme. Paris: Gallimard, 1964.
- Kuffler SW and JG Nicholls: From Neuron to Brain. Sunderland, Mass.:
Sinauer Associates, 1976.
- Kuhl PK: Perception of speech and sound in early infancy. In Handbook of
infant perception. Vol. 2 pp. 275-382. New York: Academic Press, 1987.
- Kuhl PK and AN Meltzoff: The Bimodal Perception of Speech in Infancy.
Science 218: 1138-1141, 1982.
- Kuhl PK and JD Miller: Speech perception by the chinchilla. Science, 190:
69-72. 1975.
- Lashley KS: The problem of serial order in behavior. In Cerebral
Mechanisms in Behavior. ed LA Jeffress pp. 112-135. New York: Hafner, 1951.
- Lenneberg EH: Biological foundations of Language. New York: John Wiley,
1967.
- Liberman AM: Discussion paper. In Annals of New York Academy of Sciences.
Vol 280: 718-724, 1976.
- Liberman AM et al: Perception of the speech code. Psychological Review 74:
431-461, 1967.
- Liberman AM and IG Mattingly: The motor theory of speech perception
revised. Cognition 21: 1-36, 1985.
- Lieberman P: The biology and evolution of language. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press. Comment on review in J. Acoustic Society of America
80: 1521-152, 1984.
- Lindblom BF: Economy of speech gestures. In The Production of Speech ed P
Macneilage, pp. 217-245, 1983.
- MacKay WA: The motor program: back to the computer. In The motor system in
neurobiology ed by EV Evarts, SP Wise and D Bousfield, pp. 101-106. Amsterdam:
Elsevier, 1985.
- Macneilage P ed: The Production of Speech. New York: Springer-Verlag,
1983.
- Marsden CD, JC Rothwell and BL Day: The use of peripheral feedback in the
control of movement. In The motor system in neurobiology ed by EV Evarts, SP
Wise and D Bousfield, pp. 215-212. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1985.
- McNeill D: Action, thought and language. Cognition 10: 201-208., 1981.
- Milner PM: Physiological Psychology. London: Holt, Rinehart & Winston,
1970.
- Morse PA: Speech perception in the human infant and the Rhesus monkey. In
Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences Vol. 280: 694-707, 1976.
- Nottebohm F: Vocal tract and brain: A search for evolutionary bottlenecks.
Annals of New York Academy of Sciences 280: 643-649, 1976.
- Ojemann G: Brain organisation for language from the perspective of
electrical stimulation mapping. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 189-230, 1983.
- Ojemann G and C Mateer: Human language cortex: Identification of common
sites for sequencing motor activity and speech. In Hearing Mechanisms and
Speech. ed U Creutzfeldt, H Schreich & C Schreiner, pp, 192-220. Berlin:
Springer-Verlag. 1979.
- Osgood CE: Where do sentences come from?. In Semantics: An
inter-disciplinary reader. ed. D.D. Steinberg and L.A. Jakobovits, pp.
497-529. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971.
- Penfield W and L Roberts: Speech and Brain-Mechanisms. London: Oxford
University Press, 1959.
- Phillips RE and FW Peck: Brain organisation and neuromuscular control of
vocalisation in birds. In Neural and Endocrine Aspects of Behaviour in Birds
ed by P Wright, PG Caryl and DM Vowles, pp. 243-271. Amsterdam: Elsevier,
1975.
- Pribram KH: Languages of the brain. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey:
Prentice-Hall, 1971.
- Robertson RM and KG Pearson: Neural networks controlling locomotion in
locusts. In Model networks and behavior. ed AI Selverston, pp. 21-45, 1985.
- Schmidt RA: Motor Control and Learning. Champaign, Illinois: Human
Kinetics, 1982.
- Selverston AI (ed): Model networks and behavior. New York: Plenum, 1985.
- Serebrennikov BA: Reducibility of languages of the world. In Essays on
Linguistics, Language Systems and Structures, pp. 1-56. Moscow: Progress
Publishers, 1980.
- Slobin DI: Cross-linguistic evidence for the Language-Making Capacity In
Volume 2: Theoretical Issues pp. 1157-125, 1985.
- Slobin DI (ed): The Cross-Linguistic Study of Language Acquisition.
Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum Associates, 1985.
- Sommerhoff G: Logic of the Living Brain. London: John Wiley, 1974.
- Studdert-Kennedy J: A Note on the Biology of Speech Perception. In
Perspectives on Mental Representation ed by J Mehler, ECT Walker and M
Garrett,pp. 329-338. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum Associates, 1982.
- Sutherland NS: Visual discrimination in animals. British Medical Bulletin
20: 54-59, 1964.
- Taub E P Perella and G Barro: Behavioral development after forelimb
deafferentiation. Science 181: 959-960, 1973.
- Teuber H-L: Lacunae and research approaches to them. In Brain Mechanisms
underlying Speech and Language. ed by CG Millikan and FL Darley, pp. 204-216.
New York: Grune and Stratton, 1967.
- Teuber H-L:In The motor system in neurobiology ed by EV Evarts, SP Wise
and D Bousfield, pp. 133-139 Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1985.
- Thorpe WH: Animal vocalisation and communication. In Brain Mechanisms
underlying Speech and Language. ed by CG Millikan and FL Darley, pp. 2-12. New
York: Grune and Stratton, 1967.
- Turvey MT: Preliminaries to a theory of action with reference to vision.In
Perceiving, acting and knowing. ed R Shaw and J Bransford, pp. 211-265.
Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum Associates, 1977.
- Welker W: Brain evolution in mammals. In Evolution of Brain and Behavior
in Vertebrates ed by RB Masterton, CB Campbell, ME Bitterman and N Hotton, pp.
251-344. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum Associates., 1976.
- Wind J: Phylogeny of the human vocal tract. Annals of the New York Academy
of Sciences 280: 612-630, 1976.
- Wynne Edwards VC: Evolution through Group Selection. Oxford: Blackwell
Scientific Publications, 1986.