Presuppositionalist Circularities:

My Response to Van Til's

Open Advocacy of Begging the Question

by Anton Thorn

 

Background:

The following letter was my response (with a little editing) to an individual who defended his use of fallacious question-begging in an argument in a religious chatroom on America Online. In the chatroom, I argued against the Christian apologetic method known as "presuppositionalism" for a variety of reasons. One point that I did mention in my argument was the fact that presuppositionalism commits the fallacy known as petitio principii, commonly known as begging the question (see my article on fallacies under the heading "Circularities" for details on this fallacy). My opponent, whom I shall call "Fred" in the following article, did not attempt to refute this fact, and instead simply accepted it and essentially replied, "So what?" My opponent Fred felt quite justified in basing his claims - and indeed his entire philosophic system - on a fallacious foundation. To substantiate his alleged justification, Fred sent me the following quotation from a work by Cornelius Van Til, the late Christian philosopher/apologist (known hereafter as Van Til or CVT):

We hold it to be true that circular reasoning is the only reasoning that is possible to finite man. The method of implication as outlined above is circular reasoning [the portion to which CVT refers is not given - A. Thorn]. Or we may call it spiral reasoning. We must go round and round a thing to see more of its dimensions and to know more about it, in general, unless we are larger than that which we are investigating. Unless we are larger than God we cannot reason about Him by any other way, than by a transcendental or circular argument. The refusal to admit the necessity of circular reasoning is itself an evident token of Antitheism. Reasoning in a vicious circle is the only alternative to reasoning in a circle (Van Til: Metaphysics of Apologetics, p. 12).

While I was delightedly surprised to see that Fred took the time to send me this quote after we had concluded our debate, I am far from unaware of the attitude that apologists such as Van Til take as far as justifying their base assertions, or "presuppositions". From the face of it, you, my reader, can probably spot a lot of problems with the views that CVT elucidates here. However, for those who may not see these problems, the following is given.

 

Thorn's Response:

 

Dear Fred,

Thanks for your note. I really enjoyed reading this. I have read this passage before, and I'm still just as surprised to see that intelligent people like yourself consider such positions valid and worthy of considering as knowledge. I think a passage like this is one of those points at which Van Til was careless enough to allow his slip, if you will, to show beneath his dress [1]. In other words, here he quite simply points out that his whole system is founded on a series of cognitive errors. You may think, "So what?" as you responded in the chatroom. And if that is the value you place on your mind and the things you consider knowledge, that is completely your choice and I agree that you have the right to choose such thoughts and consider them knowledge. However, the admission that they are founded on error is noted. Let's examine the passage you provided from Van Til's laborious windings and see what we can find, shall we?

"We hold it to be true that circular reasoning is the only reasoning that is possible to finite man."

Okay, noted. As already stated in past exercises, here Mr. CVT admits that he sees no alternative to informal fallacy. With these words he commits his entire system to cognitive error and makes no attempt to conceal this, as this appears to be his *real* 'ultimate presupposition'; regardless, in matters of this present quotation, CVT is treating this conclusion as his primary. I appreciate his candor; so should you. However, we must bear in mind what we are talking about. We are talking about knowledge and its validation in general. Such dialogue would have to include - either implicitly or explicitly - some reference to the nature of the being to which this matter applies. That being is, in this case, man himself. Before we can make any knowledge statements about God, we would have to first achieve some understanding about our nature and our ability to acquire and validate knowledge (you should be seeing by now the hierarchical nature of knowledge through these principles; that hierarchical nature of knowledge is key to these concerns).

Here CVT, without any attempt (at least in this little snipplet) to justify his assessment of man's nature, states that "We hold..." (who is 'we'? he does not specify here; perhaps elsewhere? does he speak for you?) "...it to be true..." (here he invokes the concept 'truth' and I would love to know what his explicit, essentialized definition of 'truth' is; so far, in my many years of Bible study, I have not been able to find an adequate definition of 'truth' in scripture; CVT may want to state it for the record [2]) "...that circular reasoning is the only reasoning that is possible to finite man." Now, here Mr. CVT makes his reference to the nature of the being to which his proceeding statements will apply: he offers a brief assessment of man and his ability to reason. He does not argue here for this conclusion; he merely asserts it as a primary that no reasoning but circular reasoning is possible to man. How does he come to that conclusion? Reference to his argument for such a conclusion is not given. Is this true simply because Mr. CVT writes it in a book? No, I don't buy it, at this point it is just an empty assertion.

Basically, what CVT does announce here is that no knowledge is possible for man except that which is arrived at through flawed thinking - i.e., circular reasoning [3]. He states that this is the only means of knowledge open to man. It appears from this single line that CVT blames man's finite nature for this narrow possibility. Do you suppose if we were to investigate CVT's prior arguments to this point that the crux of his argument for the impossibility of valid reasoning to man would contain some premise to the effect that it is man's nature as a finite being that makes this necessary? In other words, do you suppose that CVT's argument to this conclusion, that only circular reasoning is open to man, is due to the fact that man is a finite being, with finite identity, finite ability, finite access to the facts of reality? Is it the very fact that man's identity is finite that chains him to cognitive error? (This was, incidentally, Kant's argument; is CVT borrowing here?) If indeed this is the major crux of CVT's prior arguments to this point (assuming he offers any), then is he arguing that only non-identity can allow for valid reasoning? (Keep in mind that identity is necessarily finite; A is A; a corollary to the Law of Identity is the fact that, if A should exist, it MUST be A.) You may want to do a little more investigating on this matter (read before page 12 of this book from which you take your little snipplet here; I imagine you might find more clues to this epistemological imbroglio that CVT is setting up; seems he's caught another fly).

Let's continue.

 

"The method of implication as outlined above is circular reasoning [4]. Or we may call it spiral reasoning."

"Spiral reasoning"? Is CVT here trying to euphemize a cognitive error? Sure seems like it. "We don't like the sound of 'circular reasoning' because that smacks of non-validity; let's call it 'spiral reasoning'; it has a better ring to it." Well, perhaps this was not actually said in some robe room prior to some seminary dissertation, but it sure seems quite feasible, doesn't it? But let's open the hood here for a second and understand the error that CVT is committing himself and his students to.

Circular reasoning (also called 'begging the question') is an informal fallacy of presumption. "These fallacies arise not because the premises are irrelevant to the conclusion or provide insufficient reason for believing the conclusion, but because the premises presume what they purport to be true. Begging the question attempts to hide the fact that a certain premise may not be true..." (P. J. Hurley, Logic, 3rd ed., Wadsworth Publishing, Belmont, Ca., 1988, pg. 136). Later, Hurley writes under the heading "Begging the Question (Petitio Principii)":

Begging the question occurs when an arguer uses some form of phraseology that tends to conceal the questionably true character of a key premise. If the reader or listener is deceived into thinking that the key premise is true, he or she will accept the argument as sound, when in fact it may not be. Two requirements must be met for this fallacy to occur:

1. The argument must be valid. [i.e., the structure of the argument must follow rules of validity - A. Thorn]

2. Some form of phraseology must be used to conceal the questionably true character of a key premise.

The kind of phraseology used varies from argument to argument, but it often involves using the conclusion to support the questionable premise. (Ibid., 137)

Thank you, Mr. Hurley, for this clarification. Now, notice what Mr. Hurley states: "it [the fallacy of begging the question, or circular reasoning] often involves using the conclusion to support the questionable premise." Oh really? This is backwards, isn't it? Shouldn't the premises be asserted to support their conclusion rather than the other way around? Where have we seen this before? I can think of a couple examples.

Let's start out simple:

Premise 1: If the Bible states that God exists (P), then God exists (Q).

Premise 2: The Bible states that God exists (P).

Conclusion: Therefore, God exists (Q).

Simple modus ponens format: If P, then Q. P, therefore Q. The argument may be said to be valid, just as Mr. Hurley stipulated. Okay, fine. But is it true? Well, that's where the problem comes in. Look at the phraseology. See the problems? Where do you suppose the problem lies? Correct, the problem lies in the first premise. Premise 1 errs in its presumption, a classic question-begging give-away. Premise 1 presumes that the Bible is a reliable and trustworthy source of claims. However, this is not established. It is presumed. Many people accept this form of argument as sound, however, not realizing that the argument is just another instance of circular reasoning. After all, if you substituted "Koran" in place of "Bible" in the above example, you still maintain the same validity (modus ponens), but with this change you would be establishing the 'truth' of a competing religion. Would you accept the argument then? Or, does this shift only highlight the erroneous presumption involved in the original example?

By his own statements (see above), CVT seems to believe that such arguments may be accepted into the realm of knowledge. Some will say, "So what?" A mind is a terrible thing to squander.

Now let's look at another example of circular reasoning in progress:

Premise 1: If we presuppose the existence of God (P), then we can be certain that such a being exists (Q).

Premise 2: We presuppose the existence of God (P).

Conclusion: Therefore, we can be certain that God exists (:Q).

How's that one? Is this argument valid in form? Well, let's see. It seems to follow the basic pattern of modus ponens: If P, then Q. P, therefore Q. I have inserted these variables into the terms of the argument to show their position. Now, can you see how this argument is begging the question from the preceding? First, you might want to identify the troublesome phraseology. Does the argument achieve soundness? Where do you suppose is the troublesome phraseology that Hurley mentions? Perhaps some will think that there is no troublesome phraseology here, that the argument is completely sound and reliable. But does the conclusion necessarily follow from the premises? If I replace 'God' in the above syllogism with 'tooth fairy', does the argument achieve the same truth status? Or, let's see if the same soundness is achieved if we alter the argument slightly in a different manner:

Premise 1: If we presuppose the non-existence of God (P), the we can be certain that such a being does not exist (Q).

Premise 2: We presuppose the non-existence of God (P).

Conclusion: Therefore, we can be certain that God does not exist (Q).

Same format, same distribution of terms, same model of validity. In fact, this argument is completely parallel with the former with some very minor exceptions. A few terms have been varied, but the logical process is basically identical [5]. Now, it is quite humorous to note that some folx will accept the first variation as true while rejecting the second variation as false. Why is that, do you suppose? Are both sound? Are there no premises of questionably true character in either case? Do the conclusions necessarily follow the premises? Perhaps, one will say, that there are no errant presumptions in the first variation (the "pro-god's-existence" version), but that the second variation (the "con-god's-existence" version) does presume erroneous facts. How can this be? Neither argument provides a justification for either of the premises that the other does not, so we must examine each argument as equals, not conferring the benefit of the doubt to either one over the other. Agreed? No? Yes? Not sure? I'm bored and I don't want to think about this any more?

Certainly, it is quite apparent that both arguments commit the same fallacy, the same fallacy to which CVT assumes man is condemned to repeat in every task of reasoning. Calling it 'spiral reasoning' does not eliminate the problem; in fact, it is nothing short of an attempt to further conceal the problem. Why would CVT want to do this? Well, that would require a motivational analysis of CVT's intentions, but I would not be surprised if CVT were trying to protect something, such as decades of personal investment in pursuing his years of education, his chair at whatever-minster seminary and the pay it brought him year after year, not to mention the tremendous influence he garnered over young and gullible seminary students wagging their spiritual tails in agreement with every word that proceeded from his fallacy-varnished lips (by his own admission, mind you). Van Til stood to lose quite a bit if he did not offer a defense of the petty kingdom he had established through his work. Should it have been revealed that his work was in error, then all that he worked for - not to mention the borrowed self-esteem that he enjoyed from it - could quite easily have come crashing down on himself. But CVT was quite clever (and he learned this from Kant, by the way, but was grandly less sophisticated in going about it): Van Til built into his over-bloated theories the notion that man's nature necessitates that his reasoning is irreversibly flawed. A very clever thing to do, don't you think? Besides, all his little students had accepted everything else thus far, why would they not accept this? Furthermore, he had a great model, Immanuel Kant himself. If Kant could get away with it (and boy, did he!), then why can't Cornelius Van Til? Kant's task was far more impressive, for Kant snowed people into rejecting reality to spite themselves. Van Til, on the other hand, was arguing for something far 'safer' - for the existence of God and a heaven where everyone could go in the 'afterlife' and be 'happy'. Now, what could feel better than that? While Kant built a theory that offered those who accepted it absolutely no hope for happiness (in fact, those who do accept Kant's doctrines have been swindled out of their happiness as an end in itself, as this was his very purpose), Van Til worked within a far more insulated realm of constraints - god-belief - which is already popular, 'benevolent mysticism', 'eternal reward', 'hope', etc., all the accoutrements of a feel-good system, so long as you accept the system and don't care about feeling good about feeling good (more circularities!).

Let's proceed with our analysis:

"We must go round and round a thing to see more of its dimensions..."

Who is this 'we' again, that CVT keeps bringing up? Is he speaking for a small coterie of zealous sycophants and pedantic disciples? Or, does he presume this statement to include all of the human race into his quotients here? More troublesome presumptions, Mr. Van Til? They really come out of the woodwork, don't they? Now, he does use some more terminology here in this brief snipplet that may prove troublesome later. He uses the term 'dimensions' in reference to those things we *presumably* are to be reasoning about; "to see more of its *dimensions*." This will become very tricky for Van Til to maintain consistently if and when he attempts to apply the principle he is describing to arguing for his god-belief claims, for 'God' (whatever that is) is said "not to project into space". In other words, no dimensions whatsoever. Now, granted, Van Til may later tweak this term in order to sneak in some more equivocations, and his innocent pupils will likely not notice them, but I would suggest that Mr. Van Til exercise a little less carelessness here, for he's going to get himself into a lot of trouble (as if he weren't already completely lost on himself to begin with). The present indulgence of equivocation will be noted as precedent, however: "Circular reasoning" becomes a softer, more palpable term "spiral reasoning" which equivocation is seemingly justified because "we must go round and round a thing to see more of its dimensions." Pithy, but not very clear or consistent. CVT's attempts to equivocate are far from sophisticated at this point. But he does develop a little skill and dexterity in his subterfuge later on, in the proceeding chapters of the same Metaphysics of Apologetics primer.

"... and to know more about it..."

STOP! "Know more about" WHAT? Van Til speaks of a "thing". What thing? What kind of 'thing'? An existent thing? Or a non-existent thing? Does Van Til presuppose existence here? Or, should we, his readers, guess? Again, we are speaking of methods of acquiring and validating knowledge here, right? Knowledge of WHAT? Has Van Til clarified this point yet? Or is he still in orbit on this issue, skirting it with yet more and more question-begging and equivocations, hoping this question never comes up? Does it matter? Apparently not to CVT. Should it matter? Well, that would depend on what it is one is trying to prove, wouldn't it? After all, if one were to clarify that all this circularity necessitated by man's finite nature were applicable to knowledge of reality as opposed to non-reality, that would be quite a statement, don't you suppose? Then again, CVT has not clarified if the target of his circular reasoning is to be found within reality or 'outside reality'. For that matter, we are still 'in the dark' so to say as to how Mr. Van Til would define the term 'reality'. A troublesome term for most folx (the folx who wrote the Bible failed to offer a concise definition), and I suppose that this oversight on CVT's part may not be unintentional. Then again, clarification of terminology and essentialized definitions has never been a strong point among mystics.

"... in general, unless we are larger than that which we are investigating."

Again, this last point would have a lot to do with the nature of the subject matter in question. CVT does not clarify. Also, here he attempts to introduce yet another non-problem into the problem he's exploring. That is, namely, some kind of 'problem' arising out of the 'size differential' between the one employing circular reasoning (folx like CVT) and that to which this circularly reasoned knowledge is alleged to pertain. Why this is a problem, CVT does not elucidate very well, but let's note it and see where he wants to go.

"Unless we are larger than God we cannot reason about Him by any other way, than by a transcendental or circular argument."

Okay, why is that? Is this a result of the 'size differential' he introduced in the last statement? Well, if we replace the word 'God' (whatever that means) with another item (this time, one found in reality) that is definitely larger than "us", such as a mountain, would the same principle apply? Yes, no? What was the middle part? I don't follow you? Okay, let me explain. Here CVT says we would have to be 'larger than God' in order to reason about him. He does not offer a clear explanation for this conclusion, but let's not worry about that right now. Let's see how his new principle applies. I am not larger than Mt. Davidson, a large accumulation of raw matter known as a mountain or hill here in San Francisco. I am smaller than it; this mountain contains many millions of times the mass of my own body. By CVT's principle here, I would not be able to reason about it (size differential precludes this, according to the principle he is introducing here). Therefore, my recognition - based on reason - that this mountain exists in the territory known as San Francisco City and County is necessarily flawed (CVT may call it 'spiral reasoning' - an error is an error no matter what you call it; a spade is a spade; A is A) unless I arrive at it via a 'transcendental argument'? Even if I make the statement "Mt. Davidson exists" I am, according to CVT, committing an error of cognition. Why? Simply because it is bigger than me? So, when I make the assertion, "Ocean Avenue proceeds along the southern perimeter of Mt. Davidson," I am, according to CVT, in error. Again, size does matter, according to CVT. Why? Blank out.

Incidentally, if God is said not to "project into space" as so many apologists assert, and consequently has no physical form or occupies any physical dimension, how then can this non-problem - CVT's alleged 'size differential' problem - be a problem even for the theist? How can this 'problem' even be applicable, given the alleged nature of the subject matter, if the principle Van Til offers could be said to be legitimate? Is there no attempt among religious believers to make their claims at least coherent with each other?

"The refusal to admit the necessity of circular reasoning is itself an evident token of Antitheism."

Really? That's interesting. Doesn’t this sound a bit superstitious? "The refusal to admit the necessity of circular reasoning is itself an evident token of Antitheism"? [Emphasis Thorn.] This statement indeed appears to have been made in haste, for his very premise that "circular reasoning is the only reasoning possible to finite man" has yet to be established, at least in context of the present citation. CVT takes this alleged necessity as a given, which is suspicious, and then identifies the "the refusal to admit" a "token of Antitheism". Does CVT anywhere contrast "circular reasoning" with any other possible variant of reasoning? Why or why not? It should be self-evident from the fact that CVT was a devout mystic that "antitheism" - whether capitalized or not - is, in his book, an egregious evil. However, religious people have long been given to the habit of ridiculing or condemning those who do not readily accept their unsupportable claims. After all, how does one come to the conclusion that "circular reasoning" is the only kind of reasoning possible to man without itself being a conclusion based on circular reasoning?

"Reasoning in a vicious circle is the only alternative to reasoning in a circle (Van Til: Metaphysics of Apologetics, p. 12)."

Well, at least he admits it. Unfortunately for Van Til's disciples, it is unclear what the difference between "reasoning in a vicious circle" and "reasoning in a circle" is.

Thanks again, Fred, for sharing somebody else's thoughts. Would love to hear yours sometime.

 

Summary:

While the quotation cited from Van Til's book is quite slim in content, much can be ascertained from his direct statements. Van Til blatantly declares that man is doomed to presumptive error in his reasoning, yet, insofar as this citation is concerned, offers no good reason to accept that declaration. When he does try to argue this point, his statements suddenly become murky with vague approximations. Epistemology was not a matter of precision for Van Til, so it seems from his comments here. He then attempts to justify his notions by asserting a strange principle which suggests that our ability to reason somehow hinges on the size differential between the person using this reasoning and the object of his reasoning. How he justifies this principle is unknown, but does imply a conceptual disconnect in that this principle essentially signals a kind of epistemological surrender, indeed, a surrender to accepting fallacy-laden premises as one's primary, for it is by this apparently problematic size differential that necessitates what Van Til calls a 'transcendental argument'.  Just as Van Til, borrowing from Kant, argues that it is due to man's nature as a being with identity that he is doomed to 'circular reasoning', so he also uses - of all things! - man's size as a strike against the stability of his mind. In such a manner do 'intellectuals' like Van Til attempt to establish and justify their superstitions and myth-mongering. Rather than having the courage to base their conclusions on reality and therefore develop testable arguments and theories, such 'scholars' seek only to evade reality and cover their tracks behind them in the process through subterfuge, suspicious rhetoric and a fondness for using non-problems (e.g., size differentials) as the levers to their obfuscation. True to his nature as a devoted mystic, Van Til stokes the furnace of superstition by indicating that any disagreement with his conclusion is the result of "Antitheism", which, no doubt, is considered the depths of evil in his circles. Take care to consider the source!

 

Anton Thorn

 

Notes:

 [1] While this pun was originally intended to point the humorous finger toward the likes of Freud, it should be noted that a running joke among some freethinkers is the fact that those who are most opposed to homosexuality - clergy and judges - are those whose careers often require them to wear dresses, regardless of their gender. [Back]

[2] This is true. Try it yourself. Where does the Bible define 'truth'? Many biblicists argue that verses like John 14:6 offer the biblical definition of truth. John 14:6 states: "I am the way, the truth and the life…" Do the same biblicists argue that this verse also defines the words 'way' and 'life', too? Obviously, such verses presume a previously understood idea of the concept 'truth', however, it is never elucidated in the Bible. [Back]

[3] If this conclusion is to be considered knowledge, then how, according to CVT's principle, was this knowledge established? Through circular reasoning? Such tail-chasing contradictions are similar to statements like, "There are no absolutes," which itself is to be taken as an absolute. Was CVT so dense as not to see this contradiction? [Back]

[4] The "method of implication" that CVT refers to here was not included in the citation. [Back]

[5] In fact, the futility of many theistic arguments can be exposed by a simple substitution of equally questionable terms for those suggested by apologists. For instance, considering a variant of Anselm's ontological argument, a theist might argue the following:

Premise 1: If God's nature requires that he exists [P], then we can be certain that God exists [Q].

Premise 2: God's nature requires that he exists [P].

Conclusion: Therefore, we can be certain that God exists [Q].

On the face of it, the argument follows the modus ponens model for syllogism, and therefore can be said to be valid. However, the arbitrary nature of the argument should be evident from that point on. [P] in premise one makes a statement about God's nature, which presumes that God has a nature, and therefore, presumes that God exists. Hence, as Hurley's statements above demonstrate, such an argument contains a premise that assumes the conclusion has already been shown to be true - thus, begging the question. Such an argument can be said to be an attempt to define God into existence. In spite of its obvious fallacious design, such arguments are accepted by many theists, often couched in extremely contorted linguistic somersaults in order to conceal the flaw. Replace the key term, 'God' in this case, with another nonsense term, such as 'Blarko', and the error will become highlighted, and the theist will be compelled to dismiss it. Observe:

Premise 1: If Blarko's nature requires that he exists [P], then we can be certain that Blarko exists [Q].

Premise 2: Blarko's nature requires that he exists [P].

Conclusion: Therefore, we can be certain that Blarko exists [Q].

The term 'Blarko' is no less questionable than the term 'God' for those seeking genuine intellection in such matters. Indeed, this test does not destroy the argument - for the argument had no merit to begin with. This test merely exposes the presumptive error in its key premise. [Back]

 

[Back to Anton Thorn's Main Page]

 

[Back to Top]