An Introductory Critique

of Presuppositionalism

Anton Thorn

 

In the effort to fortify my overall critique of presuppositional apologetics, I consider it necessary to begin my assessment of presuppositionalism by reviewing a description of what it entails as understood by its defenders. Hence, I have chosen to examine and critique James M. Harrison's short introduction The Presuppositional Apologetic, which undertakes the task of identifying in broad terms what presuppositionalism is, what its defenders consider to be its task or purpose, and the tactics and strategies by which its practitioners hope to achieve its goal.

 

Presuppositionalist as opposed to Evidentialist Apologetics:

Mr. Harrison opens his brief essay with the following statement:

That which I will attempt to describe in this article is known as presuppositionalism. It is an apologetic method which has had the most impact in Reformed circles, and is most closely associated with Cornelius Van Till, John Frame, and the late Greg Bahnsen. [sic]

On these words I deem it safe to proceed on the basis that what I shall herein examine conforms closely to at least one presuppositionalist's understanding of what in fact presuppositionalism is. As an apologetic method of relatively recent development (each of the individuals named lived above in the 20th century), presuppositionalism is a means of defending the Christian faith, which means: a system of arguments and argumentative strategies by which believers can work to strengthen their own adherence to their god-belief and endeavor to persuade non-believers to conversion at the same time.

Presuppositional apologetics can be distinguished from more traditional apologetic methods, known broadly as "evidentialism" in contrast to presuppositionalism. The essential distinction between these two methods seems mainly to include, respectively, their starting points in the apologetic venture, their approaches to non-belief, and their assumptions about potential commonality between believers and non-believers.

As one source defines it,

The Evidentialist (that branch of Apologetics that believes there is evidence of one kind or another that demands that the unbeliever accepts not only Theism but Christian Theism) has a different task. Whereas the Presuppositionalist can deal with the matter of belief from a Dogmatic standpoint, the Evidentialist must review physical evidence in the Natural World. [1]

From the contrast identified here, the essential distinction is one of starting points: For the evidentialist approach, the starting point is the natural world, and for the presuppositionalist, the starting point is grounded in theological assumptions, which means, we shall find: no initiating reference to reality. I take "a Dogmatic standpoint" to be one which is accepted unquestioningly, which means: the surrender of one's own use of reason in the acceptance of ideational content claimed to be true by others. We shall find in my overall examination that unquestioning dogmatic commitments, commitments to ideas which have no basis in objective reality, asserted without any rational evidence, and accepted at the expense of one's own ability to reason effectively on an objective basis, are the essential anchor of presuppositionalism.

That presuppositionalism as such begins with an explicitly dogmatic bias should be no surprise, given the nature of its task and the "goods" its practitioners believe they are defending. This is announced by one of presuppositionalism's most notable personalities, apologist Greg Bahnsen, when he claims that God's "word and character are not questionable." [2] No doubt Bahnsen and those like him take their self-abnegating cue from the founder of Christianity himself, the apostle Paul, who wrote, "let God be true, but every man a liar." (Romans 3:4) Naturally, such a principle, if accepted and practiced consistently, would necessarily cause us to discount Paul, Bahnsen and virtually all believers in this code, since, they tell us, as men they are liars. After all, as a Christian and thus as someone who accepts such teaching unquestioningly, the presuppositionalist is himself attempting to persuade us to accept the very code which explicitly warns us of its very source! I am happy to heed that warning.

The issue of non-belief, according to presuppositionalism, has a two-fold problematic nature. First, it is the consequence of "sin" - or, disobedience of God's laws or commandments. If God's commandment is to believe in Him, then naturally disbelief in God constitutes an infraction of that commandment and thus results in sin. Man's metaphysical nature, claim presuppositionalists, is naturally sinful, i.e., amorally depraved.

 

Presuppositionalism and Its Condemnation of Intellectual Liberty:

Does the fact that presuppositionalism distinguishes itself from evidentialist apologetics mean that presuppositionalism dispenses completely with the use of evidence in constructing its arguments? On this point, Mr. Harrison states:

I should begin by pointing out that the Presuppositional Apologetic does not discount the use of evidences in apologetic reasoning. It does not use evidences in the traditional manner, however. By the traditional manner, I mean using evidences as an appeal to the authority of the unbeliever's autonomous reasoning.

In other words, presuppositionalism relies on supposed 'evidences' which non-believers are not likely or anticipated to accept in the first place. This admission leads to the crucial question at this point: What is the working definition of 'evidence' for that which the presuppositional apologetic asserts as evidence? And, what is the source of that definition? And what specifically is "an appeal to the authority of the unbeliever's autonomous reasoning," and what cautionary advice does the apologist have in regard to it?

Mr. Harrison claims:

The problem is, of course, that the unbeliever cannot reason autonomously.

A position which is met throughout much of presuppositionalism is the assumption that man cannot "reason autonomously," which Mr. Harrison repeats here. According to apologist James Anderson, 'autonomous' in the sense intended by presuppositional apologetics is taken to mean "that the final point of reference and interpretation is to be located in the mind of man rather than the mind of God -- man is a 'law unto himself' in the epistemological arena." [3] What Mr. Anderson's definition of this problematic term assumes is that "the final point of reference" in man's reasoning must locate itself in a mind, essentially in a form of consciousness, rather than in the facts of reality.

If "the final point of reference" to one's reasoning must find itself in a form of consciousness, of what then is that form of consciousness said to be conscious of? Consciousness is consciousness of something, which means in the present context that consciousness requires a reference point. We already know that god-belief essentially asserts the existence of a form of consciousness which must create the objects of its own consciousness, and thus god-belief essentially boils down to divine solipsism. And from a cosmological and epistemological perspective, such ideas commit at their very basis the fallacy of pure self-reference. [4]  

Thus, the view that "the final point of reference" of man's reasoning "is to be located in [either] the mind of man [or in] the mind of God," commits a false dichotomy, for it arbitrarily ignores or eliminates the facts of reality from one's selection of "final point[s] of reference." The Objectivist solution to all this is to recognize that existence holds primacy over consciousness, and that consciousness is conscious of something, which means: consciousness requires an object outside itself, and therefore the "final point of reference" to reason must also be out external to one's consciousness as well (including God's, even though by now the invalidity of the idea of God should be apparent).

To investigate the presuppositionalist idea of intellectual autonomy, I cite apologist Greg Bahnsen:

The Christian's final standard, the inspired word of God, teaches us that "the fear of the Lord is the beginning of knowledge" (Proverbs 1:7). If the apologist treats the starting point of knowledge as something other than reverence for God, then unconditional submission to the unsurpassed greatness of God's wisdom at the end of his argumentation does not really make sense. There would always be something greater than God's wisdom - namely, the supposed wisdom of one's own chosen, intellectual starting point. The word of God would necessarily (logically, if not personally) remain subordinate to that autonomous, final standard. [5]

That presuppositionalism considers intellectual autonomy as it defines it to be anathema to sound philosophical doctrine, is clear. That the definition of this term and the presuppositionalist's repugnance for what it means both assume that the Christian God exists, should also be clear.

Notice the emphasis on Proverbs 1:7 which the apologist repeats here. Notice precisely what that verse states: that emotion should hold epistemological primacy to knowledge, for it is in emotion which one must ground knowledge. It is no ordinary emotion, however, we are told by believers; "fear of God" is no emotion lacking earthshaking profundity, they claim. Indeed, philosophically the primacy of emotion over knowledge follows after the primacy of consciousness over existence; psychologically this fear is required to provide the tenor of the mind-game which accompanies god-belief. But the reversal - that knowledge should spring from emotion rather than emotion springing from new knowledge as measured against our values - is explicitly endorsed by Christian theism.

Those who defend god-belief programs are encouraged not to wince at this reversal, but to never fail in grounding his knowledge in emotion, for what follows will "not really make sense." And to caution believers and apologists that assuming any other standard to knowledge outside the emotion evoked by the Bible's claims against man's rationality should lead to the assumption of "something greater than God's wisdom" - perhaps even a healthy self-esteem - comports precisely with the apologetic system's desired internal results: a mind scared out of its wits and desperate to argue any absurdity in order to relieve the petrifying tensions induced by the fear so enshrined by such verses.

In other words, fear is the root of Christian philosophy, and thus cognition is primarily a matter of emotional compulsion, according to this view. If the believer were not compelled emotionally by Christian fear and threats of doom, then the believer's adherence to Christian doctrine would necessarily be a matter of personal volition. In other words, his commitment to Christianity would be a consequence of his epistemological and moral choices, which are here considered by presuppositionalism to be a product of man's intellectual autonomy. And here we find specifically what presuppositionalism is intended to deny and render impotent from its very foundations: Man's volitional nature. This view of man and his philosophy cannot succeed in this universe because it relies directly on one's emotions as if they were irreducible primaries, and because it blatantly abnegates the objective, hierarchical nature of knowledge and the nature of reason entirely. Hence the mystic's motivation to insist on his stolen concepts and other philosophical errors from the very outset of his philosophy. Denying identity always results in fallacy and always requires additional fallacies in order to defend such denial.

Essentially, the presuppositionalist's objection to the non-believer's intellectual autonomy amounts to a rejection of reason, for it attempts to deny the very capacity which makes reason possible for man, which is his volition. Man has the choice to use reason or to ignore, reject or confound it. Should he use reason, he must use reason by choice. As Ayn Rand explains,

Reason is the faculty that identifies and integrates the material provided by man's senses. It is a faculty that man has to exercise by choice. Thinking is not an automatic function. In any hour and issue of his life, man is free to think or to evade that effort. Thinking requires a state of full, focused awareness. The act of focusing one's consciousness is volitional. Man can focus his mind to a full, active, purposefully directed awareness of reality - or he can unfocus it and let himself drift in a semiconscious daze, merely reacting to any chance stimulus of the immediate moment, at the mercy of his undirected sensory-perceptual mechanism and of any random, associational connections it might happen to make. [6]

But can the presuppositionalist separate man's ability to reason from his choice to use reason? Can he divorce man's volition from his nature? Can the Christian's condemnation of man's nature annul his need for reason, and/or his need to embrace reason by choice? Can the presuppositionalist establish reason as proceeding from the basis of emotional compulsion, which one of the most adept and oft-quoted of Christian apologists admits to be the very basis of Christian theism?

On all accounts, Objectivism recognizes that the presuppositionalist's goal of denying man's volitional nature and the volitional nature of man's use of reason is a self-defeating endeavor, whose goal is to destroy man, not liberate him from some alleged spiritual contamination or depravity as its defenders claim. The view of man entailed in presuppositionalism is not a rational being capable of achieving happiness on earth and creating values, but its direct opposite: a mindless lump of flesh wracked with inescapable guilt and destined for an eternity of torment.

This is consistent with Rand's eloquent identification of the biblical idea of man as given in the Genesis myth:

What is the nature of the guilt that your teacher's call [man's] Original Sin? What are the evils man acquired when he fell from the state they consider perfection? Their myth declares that he ate the fruit of the tree of knowledge - he acquired a mind and became a rationaal being. It was the knowledge of good and evil - he became a moral being. He was sentenced to earn his bread by his labor - he became a productive being. He was sentenced to experience desire - he acquired the capacity of sexual enjoyment. The evils for which they damn him are reason, morality, creativeness, joy - all the cardinal virtues of his existence. It is not his vices that their myth of man's fall is designed to explain and condemn, it is not his errors that they hold as his guilt, but the essence of his nature as man. Whatever he was - that robot in the Garden of Eden, who existed without mind, without values, without labor, without love - he was not man. [7]

It is no surprise that the mystic, in the defense of his religious claims, will insist that others reject their capacity to reason. After all, Kant himself admitted that he must "deny knowledge in order to make room for faith." [8]

Now ask what motivates the presuppositionalist's insistence on verses like Proverbs 1:7. Bahnsen states it quite clearly: that man should discount his own ability to reason ("autonomous reasoning"), and submit his mind to others in unquestioning obedience. This obedience is to be practiced, not in the interest of achieving some legitimate goal (indeed, a rational man achieves his values, not as a dependent on others, but by relying on the verdicts of his own free and uncoerced mind), but out of "fear and trembling" (cf. Ephesians 6:5, et al.).

Read for "unconditional submission to the unsurpassed greatness of God's wisdom" as unquestioning acceptance of biblical claims and assertions, even if such unquestioning submission should proceed at the expense of objectivity (which all such mysticism will ultimately require of an individual). Thus, what presuppositionalism seeks in man is not a rational being, but a mindless robot, just as we find in the Adam of the Genesis myth. Essentially it says to man: "Don't think that you can reason on your own to discover truth, we already possess it, just believe what we tell you."

And what exactly does this accomplish? Essentially one thing: To disable man's mind and reduce him to a willing victim ready for any demagogue who comes along and claims to have "the answer" to the despair and emptiness the acceptance of such views fosters in his life. Once these anti-rational, anti-human premises are accepted in the place of reason and knowledge of reality, any man will have no defense against any Witch Doctor who seeks to fill the vacuum where before he had the potential for an independent mind and a life of value achievement. This is not a doctrine of love and mercy, as it defenders claim, but a doctrine of misery and envy. And to counteract the believer's recognition of the nature of such doctrines, he is told that man can never have an independent mind, and that to aspire to any reasoning disapproved by those dictating the doctrine is a mortal sin.

Now the goal for the presuppositionalist is, to turn those who do not believe into those who do. And to do this he will begin by attacking the non-believer's independent mind, condemning it precisely for what it is. But can the apologist claim that "the unbeliever cannot reason autonomously" to be true apart from simply assuming it to be the case? What we have here is a tangled web of assumptions which are deeply interdependent upon each other, but which cannot be coherently established without the presumption of the primacy of consciousness view of reality, which is both false and integral to Christian theism.

Mr. Harrison claims:

Without God, there would be no possibility of reason.

This is essentially a mere assertion which the apologist must prove in order for it to have any intellectual merit whatsoever. Simply asserting this claim does not make it true. But notice how ironic this statement is in light of the foregoing discussion. Man's ability to reason independently from others is not in dispute for the Objectivist. However, it is for the presuppositionalist. Since Christianity (and therefore presuppositionalism) essentially considers man to be a mindless robot, as we saw above, its defenders set before themselves the task of reducing those who do think and reason independently of others, to the robot-like victims (the Bible's metaphoric use of "sheep" for its believers is no accident) it enshrines as the initial model for man, which is Adam. While the presuppositionalist holds that "without God, there would be no possibility of reason," he defends a system of philosophy which destroys man's ability to reason at its very roots: by claiming that he must surrender his mind to unconditional submission, and by rooting his knowledge in referenceless, contentless emotions.

Mr. Harrison now repeats a common presuppositionalist claim:

And so the reality of the matter is that every time the unbeliever attempts to reason, he is borrowing from the Christian worldview.

The truth of this claim depends on the supposed truth of a number of assumptions, which include, for instance:

  1. the assumption that the existence of the Christian God has been proven
  2. the assumption that reason is necessarily and inextirpably tied to the existence of the Christian God
  3. the assumption that one has awareness of the existence of Christian God

How does the apologist demonstrate that assumption 1) is warranted? Where is the claim that the Christian God exists proven to be fact? Where is the apologist's proof?

How does the apologist demonstrate that assumption 2) is warranted? What exactly is the connection between the Christian God and reason? And for that matter, what is the apologist's working definition of reason? What is the source of that definition? Is the source of that definition found in the Bible? If so, in which book, chapter and verse is that definition found? If the definition of reason preferred by the apologist is not found in the Bible, then what is its source? Is the source something admitted by the apologist to have been written by men? If so, why should this definition be accepted, particularly in light of the apologist's own declared premise, that man cannot reason autonomously? [9]

And finally, how does the apologist demonstrate that assumption 3) is warranted? The apologist claims that all men are aware of God's existence, but, citing verses like Romans 1:20-21, that men are prone to "suppress" this awareness. What are the means of this alleged awareness? How does the apologist prove that I am aware of God, when I know that I am aware of no such being, neither have I any means of being aware of anything supernatural? Indeed, the assertion of the supernatural is always arbitrary and always premature.

Moreover, how can it be the case that I am “borrowing from the Christian worldview” when I make no appeals to any supernatural beings in order to discover truths about reality and affirm them in my understanding of the world? I make no appeals to an omniscient creator which fashioned the world according to some preconceived design, and the metaphysics of my worldview are completely at odds with such assumptions, by virtue of its commitment to the primacy of existence. Harrison has taken a slogan that has been popularized in the apologetic literature of the presuppositionalists and repeated it as if it needed no further defense. Apparently it’s supposed to be true because he repeats it. This is apologetics by means of creedal recitation. No argument is given, no evidence is produced, no proof is forthcoming.

But in spite of these problems, Harrison insists that as a non-believer I am internally conflicted: 

That is, he is being inconsistent with his stated presuppositions.

And here is where the presuppositionalist's presuppositions become blatantly presumptuous. For here he presumes to insert into the mouths of non-believers philosophical ideas to which they are supposedly committed by virtue of their rejection of Christianity. This is quite amazing. Which presuppositions has the atheist stated, and how can the believer presume that he is being inconsistent with those presuppositions? The apologist still has not proven that there is a God, nor does he ever do this. Instead, he continues to attack non-believers as if this "proven fact" of God's existence were clearly apparent to all. This, however, is not the case. The apologist here attempts to cut in line, so to say, as if owning up to the onus of proving his own claims were unnecessary, superfluous or simply not required.

And that is the crucial point.

The "crucial point" is that the non-believer "is being inconsistent with his stated presuppositions"? It is one thing for a non-believer to be shown to be inconsistent with any of his implicitly or explicitly held premises, an entirely different matter for those who claim that God exists to prove this claim. Demonstrating that a non-believer is inconsistent with his own premises does not prove that God exists, nor can such a demonstration substitute for such a proof. If the apologist's only goal is to demonstrate some inconsistency on the part of others, then he fails to accept the onus of proving his own extraordinary claims, and this in itself should raise a red flag for those who expect intellectual integrity from one's supposed philosophic rivals.

Ultimately the intellectual conflict between believers and unbelievers is a matter of antithetical worldviews.

Such a comparison depends on the fundamentals of the worldviews to which any two individuals ascribe, assuming they are different. In particular, how does one's worldview address the issue of metaphysical primacy? Indeed, does one's worldview even demonstrate explicit awareness of this fundamental and inescapable issue, or must any position on this issue be inferred from loftier philosophical ideas which arise if this issue is only implicitly acknowledged while one's position on this matter remains unclearly assumed? Where for instance does the New Testament author Paul address the issue of metaphysical primacy in any certain, explicit and self-conscious terms, and is Christian theism as a whole consistent with any position on whichever position on this issue can be inferred or derived from Paul's writings? I personally have pored over Paul's writings in the New Testament, and nowhere does Paul articulate any explicitly informed position on the issue of metaphysical primacy (indeed, he expresses no explicit awareness for this issue as such anywhere in his writings), and what can be derived or inferred from Paul's writings is at best a hazy understanding of the issues at stake. However, his writings graphically affirm the primacy of consciousness of reality, which is false, and which chokes religious philosophy throughout.

Furthermore, it may be the case that a particular non-believer may reject Christian theism, but may still assume the primacy of consciousness and thus share a common basis with Christian theism at the expense of objectivity. This is far from uncommon in our culture today, because of the influence of the explicit subjectivism and mysticism of Christianity and errant philosophies akin to it.

The essence of the Presuppositional Apologetic is the attempt to show that the unbeliever's worldview drives him to subjectivity, irrationalism, and moral anarchy.

Indeed, subjectivity, irrationalism and moral anarchy which most of those who are hindered by such philosophical vices inherited from Christianity in the first place! But what should be noted here is that the "essence of the Presuppositional Apologetic" - according to this sympathetic source, preoccupies itself with what others presumably hold as true, not with substantiating its own philosophical positions and meeting the burden of proving its god-belief claims. The establishment of Reformed Christian theism is, for the presuppositionalist, a foregone conclusion lacking rational merit and positive argumentative support. Presuppositionalism can thus be seen as a negating device through and through, not a device to identify truth.

 

Rising to the Challenge: Worldviews Side-by-Side

Mr. Harrison makes the following clarification of the presuppositional method:

And so the Presuppositional Apologetic calls for the Christian and non-Christian to set side by side their two worldviews and do an internal examination of them both in order to determine whether or not they are consistent even within their own framework.

This is a great idea, and a challenge to which I exhort all Christian apologists to rise. Below I offer an at-a-glance chart outlining Christian theism as opposed to Objectivism, the philosophy of Reason:

 

                                                  

CHRISTIANITY

PHILSOPHICAL

DOCTRINE

OBJECTIVISM

Subjective (product of consciousness)

Nature of Reality

Objective, (existence is independent of consciousness)

Created by consciousness, non-absolute, secondary

Nature of Existence

Absolute, uncreated, indestructible, primary

Primacy of Consciousness

Metaphysical Primacy

Primacy of Existence

Object of creation and subject to conscious revision

Laws of Nature

Axiomatic - rooted in fact, undeniable and inescapable

Total Depravity

The Nature of Man

Volitional Rationality

Creative, reality-shaping, metaphysically active

Nature of Consciousness

Awareness, Identification, metaphysically passive

Creates its objects

Activity of consciousness

Perceives its objects

"Fear God" (mystical presuppositions; Prov. 1:7)

Cognitive starting point

of knowledge

Existence exists (Objectivist axioms)

Alleged historical events, secondhand

Substance of Philosophy

Facts of reality, firsthand

Man serves the philosophy

Rôle of Philosophy for Man

Philosophy serves Man

Stolen concepts, frozen abstractions, compart-mentalized primaries, etc.

Nature of knowledge

Hierarchical, contextual and integrated reference to reality

Alleged revelations, knowledge by no means

Source of knowledge

Perceptual contact with existence

Mysticism (whose method is faith)

Means of Knowledge

Reason (whose method is logic)

Threats:

"believe, or go to hell"

Validation

"Look at reality"

(hierarchical reduction)

Self-sacrifice

Ethics

Self-interest

Faith

Knowledge of Morality

Rationality

Mystical Beliefs and obedience

Means of Morality

Rational Principle in Action

Humility

Virtue

Pride

Achievement of approval

Purpose of Virtue

Achievement of values

Faith, Obedience, self-sacrifice

Cardinal Values

Reason, Purpose, Self-esteem

Man as a Means to the Ends of Others

The Good

Man as an End in Himself

Denial of Oneself; suffering; death

Man's Goal

Achievement of value; Happiness

Collectivism

Politics

Capitalism

Individual must sacrifice himself to the collective (e.g., the churchgoer)

Practice

Individual has the right to exist for his own sake

(e.g., the businessman)

Enshrinement of the incomprehensible

Esthetics

Concretization of one's own values

         

Above we see precisely what the apologist asks for: a side-by-side comparison of the major tenets of Christianity and Objectivism. Let us examine each briefly, one by one.

Under the headings "Nature of Reality" and "Nature of Existence," we find that Christianity considers reality to be subjective, while Objectivism considers reality to be objective. Subjectivism in metaphysics is the view that existence finds its source in a form or act of consciousness. This view is explicitly stated in the Christian doctrine of creation - the view that the world and the cosmos, i.e., the universe, were created by the "supreme being's divine will," i.e., by an act of consciousness. Reality, according to this view, is a derivative, not a primary, and subject to revision by the will of the ruling consciousness, which according to Christianity is God.

If existence is a product of conscious creation, then it cannot be fundamental, primary or absolute. Instead, it must be secondary and non-absolute, again subject to revision by the ruling consciousness. [10]

If, according to Christianity, reality (i.e., the realm of existence) finds its source in a form or act of consciousness, then reality cannot be the Christian's cognitive starting point. Consequently, the believer must assert God (i.e., a form of consciousness) as metaphysically primary, and his fear of God as his cognitive starting point, the one factor which guides and tempers the believer's thinking (if it can be called that), just as Paul exhorts believers to "bring every thought captive to the obedience of Christ" (II Corinthians 10:5). Christ, argues apologist Greg Bahnsen, "must be the ultimate authority over our philosophy, our reasoning, and our argumentation -- not just at the end, but at the beginning, of the apologetical endeavor." [11] This is why we saw Bahnsen emphasize the knowledge-emotion reversal entailed by Proverbs 1:7 above. Miss Rand eloquently pointed out the cause of this fear when she wrote, "When men abandon reason, they find that not only that their emotions cannot guide them, but that they can experience no emotions save one: terror." [12] The cause of this terror is deliberately misidentified as "God" and the religious doctrines of god-belief assume the task of guiding believers where their emotions have failed them.

If the nature of reality is subjective (i.e., a product of a form or act of consciousness), and the nature of existence is secondary to that consciousness, then consciousness holds metaphysical primacy over existence, since existence (reality) must ultimately be thought to conform to the will of consciousness (either man's or God's or both). Thus, Christian theism explicitly endorses the primacy of consciousness, even though its theologians and apologists resist this identification.

On the other hand, in all philosophical matters, Objectivism recognizes the primacy of existence, which holds that existence exists independent of consciousness (e.g., the facts of reality are facts of reality regardless of one's conscious functions or desires), that existence is absolute, uncreated, indestructible and primary, and that consciousness is consciousness of something, i.e., of existence. Which means: consciousness is not independent of existence, which means that consciousness presupposes existence, as recognized by the question: Consciousness of what?

While Objectivism holds that at least implicit recognition of the primacy of existence is unavoidable in all cognition, Christian theism holds that cognition is doomed ultimately to failure if it does not somehow reduce to the subjective commitments of Christian metaphysics (hence the development of presuppositionalism). And here the Christian can be shown to contradict himself, for in order to claim that Christianity is true, he must assume that truth is independent of consciousness, thus implicitly inferring the primacy of existence. But what the Christian claims to be true is the primacy of consciousness, which is in contradiction to the primacy of existence. Thus even to claim that "God exists," the Christian contradicts himself. [13]

The apologist, perhaps sensing these problems internal to Christianity, attempts to get around them by claiming that the ultimate source of his knowledge is divine revelation, which precludes objectivity by preempting the rôle of perception in man's initial cognitive steps in forming his first philosophy (i.e., in determining essentials, the nature of existence, the nature of man, the nature of consciousness, the nature of knowledge, etc.). As a result, alleged historical events (e.g., the creation and fall of Adam, worldwide flood, Abrahamic covenants, Mosaic stutterings, monarchical decrees, allegedly fulfilled prophecies, virgin births, resurrections, miraculous healings, etc.) are asserted as superior to the perceptual facts of reality as pertinent to the formation of a comprehensive view of life. Thus, we find that the thrust of many apologetic tactics emphasizes issues calling on the non-believer's certainty in his ability to identify the facts of reality and to deduce from them principles relevant to living his life. [14]  Thus, the actual "substance" which informs Christian philosophy are the alleged historical events claimed to have occurred in the Old and New Testaments. Even the apostle Paul acknowledges this to be the case with Christianity when he writes, "if Christ be not risen [i.e., if the alleged history of Christ's resurrection is false], then is our preaching vain, and your faith is also vain [i.e., the whole Christian theistic philosophy is invalid]." (I Corinthians 15:14) [15]

In contradistinction to this view of philosophy, Objectivism holds true regardless of what historical events have taken place, alleged or actual. For no matter whatever event has occurred or when - 20, 200 or 2000 years ago, it is still an undeniable, fundamental fact that existence exists, that to exist is to be something (i.e., that existence is identity), that consciousness is not the creator of reality, but a perceiver of the objects which exist, that consciousness has an objective identity and that man's reason requires that he begin with the perceptually self-evident facts of reality. These facts, which form the basis of the philosophy of reason, are not dependent upon the legitimacy of some claimed historical event. On the contrary, one cannot even begin to comprehend historical claims without taking these facts at least implicitly for granted.

The insistence that alleged historical events should hold priority over the facts of reality which are available to man through his own perception and reasoning, amounts to the view that the only proper philosophy is that which is acquired secondhand (or third- and fourth-hand). That secondhand (or further removed) allegations and stories should hold primacy over those facts which are presently available to man through his perception means that he must be willing to abandon his own reasoning in order to accept what he's been told is true. Thus, reason is jettisoned in favor of faith, and irrationality is embraced in reason's place.

Moving along in our side-by-side comparison of Christianity with Objectivism, we come to the question of what is the nature and source of knowledge. Of course, when considering such questions as what is the nature and source of knowledge, an obvious question which is often overlooked and unattended is the question, Knowledge of what? For Objectivism, knowledge is knowledge of reality, or, knowledge of existence. By addressing such a question from the outset, we recognize the object of our epistemological pursuits, in this case the facts of reality themselves, and this in turn helps us identify the nature of that knowledge and how we come to know it.

It is unlikely that seasoned apologists for religious philosophies will claim that the object of their knowledge is the unreal or the non-existent. So when pressed on such matters, it is anticipated that the apologist will also claim that his knowledge is, like the Objectivist's, knowledge of reality as well (though I have not seen this stated by defenders of theistic philosophies myself). This then brings us to the question of what the religious believer considers to be reality, how 'reality' is defined, and by what means it is discovered and identified. But already above we saw that the theist holds reality to be a creation, that reality is created by a form of consciousness, since existence according to Christianity (and its theistic cousins) finds its source in a form of consciousness. Thus, for the Christian, if reality is a creation of God, then knowledge is invention, not identification. And the unraveling (I dare say evolution) of this invented knowledge is the task of theology proper. For "ultimate knowledge," claim many apologists, is knowledge of God, and, as we discover through Objectivism, God is the creation of men, not the other way around (hence so many fractious internal debates within close religious quarters causing division and evasion among even creed-driven religious institutions).

In Objectivism we learn of the principle of the primacy of the what over the how, which means: the means by which we are attempting to discover and identify something are determined by and subordinate to the identity of that something. This epistemological prioritization is an extension of the primacy of existence, that the what (existence) holds primacy over the how (the means) of cognition (i.e., of consciousness). This is not a license to use reason in some cases and abandon it in others (as some apologists would have it; think of the so-called “crackers in the pantry” fallacy which Bahnsen accuses Gordon Stein of committing in their debate). Rather, the nature of the object(s) whose identity is sought to be understood determines how one should apply his reason in achieving the goal of such knowledge. Thus, the process by which knowledge of reality is achieved is consistent with the metaphysical roots of the view of reality which enables it. If, for instance, what an individual seeks to determine is the distance between two planetary bodies (the what of his epistemological quest), he naturally must employ a means which will enable him to discover this, such as a telescope. If he seeks to determine how two molecules interact under certain conditions, an electron microscope may be the proper tool. Both telescopes and electron microscopes are means of extending man’s perceptual faculty beyond their unaided ability. Thus, the Objectivist view of knowledge is completely consistent with its view of reality, that existence holds metaphysical primacy over consciousness.

In the case of religion, however, the means of acquiring knowledge commits a reversal of objectivity, just as its view of reality is a reversal of metaphysical Objectivism. Religion’s epistemology, to the extent that it can be said to have any epistemology, essentially embodies the primacy of one’s hopes over what actually exists, and therefore over what is actually true. This is where ‘faith’ comes in: it allows the believer to ignore the facts of reality and point to an elaborate fantasy in their place. There is no concept of objectivity here, for the objects of consciousness vary according to what consciousness desires them to be. A stick is a staff one moment, a slithering serpent the next. A man is blind one moment, and seeing the next. Pots are full of water one moment, and wine the next. What makes these alterations possible? According to reality, a consciousness endowed with sufficient faith: it wants these things to be the case, and they obey accordingly. For proving and validating his claims, the theist appeals to threats or to apologetic treatments, such as "transcendental arguments," which are no more arguments whose task it is to establish the truth of some allegation than they are means of undermining the psychological confidence of non-believers and "persuading" them to consider the assaults used in this effort as philosophically valid.

All of these points, the religious and the Objectivist, follow as a matter of course from their respective premises and fundamental view of existence. Hence the apologist will claim that his presuppositional beliefs exhibit a consistency unknown to non-believers, for indeed he is as consistent as he dare can be to the primacy of consciousness roots of his god-belief. For not only does he proceed philosophically on the assumption that presumed knowledge equals valid knowledge (as if consciousness could dictate at whim what standard knowledge should presume), he proceeds apologetically on the assumption that persuading others of his god-belief claims can substitute for proof of those claims; that so long as others accept his claims, he must be arguing efficiently to the truth.

So here we have precisely what the apologist himself invites, a side-by-side comparison between his worldview (Christianity) and that of the consistently rational atheist (Objectivism). It is unlikely that most apologists will accept the terms so far given, for they indeed stifle the stereotypical atheist which most apologists have been groomed to expect, and which the presuppositional apologetic strategies have been groomed to parody, in an encounter with a non-believer. But suffice it to say, we have now identified what in Christian theism constitutes a threat to man's mind, as well as the means by which he can protect himself from that threat. [16]

Harrison demonstrates the dogmatic nature of presuppositionalism’s basis with statements such as the following:

Since God does exist, and since Christianity is true, then any worldview which denies these truths are false and can be demonstrated to be so.

Again, such a statement depends on an enormous set of assumptions, both explicitly and implicitly held by the apologist. He would do well to check his premises objectively. [17]

  

The Baiting Nature of Presuppositionalism:

Consider deeply the following two paragraphs:

And so, on a practical basis, the first thing to do in a Presuppositional Apologetic is just that which an evidential apologist would not spend a great amount of time on. We listen. We let the unbeliever talk and we let him describe his worldview (i.e., the nature of reality, how the world operates, where it came from, man's place in the world, man's nature, the absence or existence of moral absolutes and the foundation of such, how do we know things and can we know things with certainty, etc.).

The more the unbeliever talks, the more we have to work with. Since his worldview is objectively false, it of necessity contains contradictions (i.e., morality is relative, but he does not live his life on that basis). Morality is absolute, but he cannot account for absolutes without God. We can have knowledge through empirical observation, but he cannot empirically observe that he can have knowledge through empirical observation, etc.

Here we find the heart of the presuppositionalist's apologetic strategy. Notice how, according to the presuppositionalist's own words, the emphasis and purpose of his apologetic is not to establish a proof for the sake of establishing the truth of his claims to the non-believer. Instead, the emphasis lies explicitly in criticizing the non-believer for his views, waiting like a spider for a fly to entrap himself in his web of deception, dishonesty, reversal and fallacy.

What should be clear here is that the emphasis of the presuppositionalist strategy is on discrediting non-theism by presumably uncovering a particular individual non-theist's ignorance or lack of understanding of particular issues in philosophy. Not only does this strategy proceed on the unproven presupposition that all worldviews outside the Reformed Christian philosophy are "objectively false," it betrays this apologetic method's reluctance to meet the burden of proving its own god-belief claims. This evasion is encountered throughout the presuppositional apologetic.

This discrediting process is initialized by literally baiting the non-believer into verbalizing both the fundamentals as well as the finer points of his worldview, something which most individuals are (both unfortunately and understandably) unprepared to do, be they theist or atheist. In the case of those non-believers who are untutored in the weightier issues of philosophy - and this describes a vast majority of people, such individuals can be "easy pickins" for craftier apologists.

Mr. Harrison here announces that apologists should be keenly aware of any opportunity in which they can goad a prospective proselyte into philosophically tripping himself up as apologists "let him describe his worldview." The use of recondite, sesquipedalian jargon, which is the calling card of many a presuppositionalist (the more academic apologists love to season their rhetoric with dashes of Latin), provides the apologist with a convenient means of bamboozling non-believers into unintentional - and perhaps inaccurate and unrepresentative - self-incrimination and philosophical confusion. The apologetic encounter, for the presuppositionalist, can be likened to a wolf zeroing in on his prey. The ensuing philosophical carnage, to continue the metaphor, is indeed gruesome.

Does the apologist presume that the non-believer faced with the challenge of providing a foolproof, yet thumbnail sketch of his worldview, will entrap himself without the apologist's own assistance? Mr. Harrison's own statements - "…We listen. We let the unbeliever talk and we let him describe his worldview…" - suggests that the apologist is ready to assume a passive rôle in the apologetic encounter. But why should one accept this implied assumption, if indeed this is in the back of Mr. Harrison's - or any other presuppositionalist's - mind? After all, the apologist has a dedicated investment to protect, which is his god-belief and its associated psychological fallout.

On the contrary, the apologist’s tactic is not to listen, but to bait and coax, to manipulate and to entrap. In fact, listening is precisely what they tend not to do, at least not charitably. If they listen, they listen only as a means of gathering material that can be refashioned into easily demolished stunt doubles. The presuppositionalist’s apologetic practice exposes his true ambition. It is not to understand his opponent’s position and reason with him, as if he truly cared for his intellectual integrity. On the contrary, that intention is to destroy his self-esteem, his purpose and his confidence in his ability to reason. Compromise a man’s integrity to the point that it collapses into a shapeless goo, and you have the perfect candidate for the enslavement of god-belief.

It is upon this rubble – what used to be human – that Harrison affirms that "morality is absolute." Objectivism agrees that morality is absolute - though for reasons which differ radically from any theistic view of morality. It certainly does not agree with Harrison’s claim that one "cannot account for absolutes without God." Not only does Objectivism recognize that appealing to any form of supernaturalism is unnecessary and irrelevant to metaphysical, epistemological and moral absolutes, it also points out the fact that no assertion of absolutes can be consistently defended on the false metaphysics entailed by god-belief, which is the primacy of consciousness view of reality.

Objectivism’s view of absolutes illustrates the fundamentality of its opposition to the religious view of the world. According to Objectivism, absolutes are not provided by consciousness. On the contrary, they are discovered, identified and understood by means of consciousness. Metaphysically, absolutes are already implied in perception and the derivation of axiomatic concepts, which are perceptually based. The axiom rooting Objectivism is: Existence exists. Objectivism recognizes the axiomatic concept 'existence' - which is the broadest of all concepts - as essential to all concepts. The fact of existence is absolute and inescapable. Also, the fact that existence exists does not change. What "accounts for" the absolute nature of existence is simply the fact that existence exists. To point to something "prior to" the fact of existence in order to "account for" it results in the fallacy of the stolen concept, since the concept 'existence' must be presupposed by all other concepts, including the concept 'consciousness', which is the most commonly assumed stolen concept in all theistic metaphysics. It is this fallacy which often eludes non-objective philosophical detection, since most people are unaware of the objective view of concepts. And since the metaphysical starting point for theism is as such fallacious in nature, any appeal to absolutes, either epistemological or moral, is consequently compromised and rationally indefensible.

It is in the fact of existence, the starting point of Objectivism, that an objective view of epistemological and moral absolutes finds its ultimate basis. This fact is available to all men through perception and the process of objective cognition. It is not an idea shrouded in mystery and incomprehensibility and claimed to be the product of supernatural revelation, to which only "the chosen" have access. These are the hallmarks of mysticism, not objectivity. Suffice it to say, the apologist, most likely due to utter ignorance of Objectivism, is way off the mark in this regard. [18]

When Mr. Harrison states that, "We can have knowledge through empirical observation, but he cannot empirically observe that he can have knowledge through empirical observation...," he ignores a crucial distinction between the perceptual and the conceptual levels of man's consciousness. The perceptual level of man's consciousness, on one hand, is not a volitional form of consciousness. Man cannot choose to feel pleasure when he passes his finger through a flame any more than he can choose to see Michelangelo's David in place of Munch's The Scream. Man's conceptual faculty, on the other hand, is volitional in nature, as it can be directed by conscious self-regulation and involves an act of selection from among the data he perceives. This point is that man's

senses cannot deceive him, that physical objects cannot act without causes, that his organs of perception are physical and have no volition, no power to invent or distort, that the evidence they give him is an absolute, but his mind must learn to understand it, his mind must discover the nature, the causes, the full context of his sensory material, his mind must identify the things that he perceives. [19]

Common attacks against the validity of the senses often include pencils which appear "bent" when placed in a glass of water. But such attacks themselves must assume the validity of the sensation, for how else would one know that a pencil is actually straight in the first place? The fact that we perceive what appears to be a distortion in the pencil's shape only testifies that perception provides a "full context" of data, including light refraction, of the objects we perceive. The context of our perception, however, once we get to the conceptual level of consciousness, can be accepted or rejected in the formation of our ideas and concepts.

That man can gain knowledge through his perception while not being able to "empirically observe that he can have knowledge through empirical observation," is not problematic for Objectivism. As Dr. Harry Binswanger argues:

The processing that underlies perception is neurophysiological and nonintrospectible. When a child sees a table, he is unaware of the neurophysiological processes, from the retina on up, that make the percept [of the table] possible, and he had no choice in the control over the development of those processes; the percept is for him a direct "given" rather than the product of inference or interpretation. We learn of the existence of sensory processes only extrospectively, by scientific investigation. [20]

These reasons only underscore and support the overall view of knowledge informed by Objectivism. While apologists for philosophies detrimental to man's mind point to such facts as inconsistencies plaguing certain views, Objectivism recognizes that such facts are consistent with the objective view of reality and knowledge informed by its foundations.

It must be borne in mind that, in general, many presuppositionalists take delight when non-believers doubt the verdicts of their own mind, particularly when those verdicts are inconsistent with Christian mysticism, and when they doubt the foundations of their thought and the methods they incorporate in their thinking. What the presuppositionalist seeks to disable is the non-believer's ability to achieve certainty, particularly in fundamentals, and his confidence in any means by which he achieves any certainty. Quite often, presuppositionalists will deny that man's perception facilitates a fundamental rôle in the achievement of knowledge, arguing essentially that even perception as such is not valid without certain conscious preconditions (or "presuppositions") already in place (such as the assumption that nature is uniform, etc.).

This kind of argument is the residue of a devastating but still common misunderstanding in philosophy, made popular by Immanuel Kant (whose professed goal was to save religion, mind you). That misunderstanding is the notion that percepts - the material provided by the senses, are "imported conceptually" into man's consciousness. This view ultimately reduces both to the notion that existence finds its source in a form of consciousness (i.e., metaphysical subjectivism) - as the perception of reality (i.e., what we perceive) is thought to originate in the mind ("imported conceptually"), and to a co-operating fundamental error called the fallacy of pure self-reference (since consciousness is said to be supplying its own content divorced from any contact outside itself - because percepts are "imported conceptually").

Objectivism corrects this error and finds support for its position in science:

The truth is that the perceptual level is not imported conceptually, it is not constructed consciously, it's produced automatically, without knowledge, without effort, without conscious direction by the brain. The movement to the perceptual level [from the sensory level] is a physical, not a conscious [and consequently, not a volitional], integration. To reach the perceptual level is a neurological development. To experience entities requires the growth of nerve cells that connect with each other in a certain way. Now the progression from sensations to percepts does require sensory input. The brain will not develop the ability to produce percepts if the organism is raised in a totally dark environment [i.e., without anything to sense]. Experiments have shown that. [21]  

In other words, without sensory contact with existence, one's perceptual faculty will produce nothing. And if one's perceptual faculty does not produce percepts, there will be no content for the conceptual faculty (i.e., cognition) to identify. Thus, I side with Miss Rand when she stated that the "arguments of those who attack the senses are merely variants of the fallacy of the 'stolen concept'." [22] And it is this fallacy, the stolen concept, which plagues presuppositional apologetics from the core of its foundations.

Mr. Harrison summarizes the basic ambition of presuppositionalism for rebuffing criticism of Christianity:

We also demonstrate that whatever objections he may have against Christianity are either a misunderstanding of true Christianity, or that they are not legitimate objections within the Christian worldview.

Harrison wants to sew the seed in the minds of budding apologists that, no matter what the substance of a non-believer’s criticism of Christianity may be, it will fit within one of the two categories he gives here. This is an example of how presuppositionalism encourages its users to bypass a most crucial step in the process of knowledge acquisition – namely the step known as discovery – in preference for pre-cognizing any objection within a set of pre-cast alternatives which play to Christianity’s larger purposes. For even before the apologist has had a chance to field a criticism, it’s already been pigeonholed into one of two innocuous categories. The formula that Harrison offers here is easy to master: if someone raises an objection to Christianity, dismiss it as “either a misunderstanding of true Christianity” (whatever that might possibly be), or as failing to qualify as “legitimate objections within the Christian worldview.” In regard to the first arm of this tactic, Anthony Gottlieb points out:

One practical problem for antireligious writers is the diversity of religious views. However carefully a skeptic frames his attacks, he will be told that what people in fact believe is something different. For example, when Terry Eagleton, a British critic who has been a professor of English at Oxford, lambasted Dawkins’s “The God Delusion” in the London Review of Books, he wrote that “card-carrying rationalists” like Dawkins “invariably come up with vulgar caricatures of religious faith that would make a first-year theology student wince.” That is unfair, because millions of the faithful around the world believe things that would make a first-year theology student wince. A large survey in 2001 found that more than half of American Catholics, Episcopalians, Lutherans, Methodists, and Presbyterians believed that Jesus sinned—thus rejecting a central dogma of their own churches. [23]

In other words, the apologist can always respond to an objection by saying “that’s not what we believe!” (Watch for the “we” expressions in such cases; the use of the plural here is often an attempt to inflate numbers for their intimidating effect.) Such protestations are typically followed by contemptuous aspersions to the effect that only an ignoramus would think that Christians would endorse the view in question.

As for Harrison’s category of “legitimate objections within the Christian worldview,” what could possibly qualify as this while at the same time being critical of Christianity? Naturally Harrison does not anticipate this kind of question, for he offers no indication of what Christianity as a worldview might consider as a challenge to it as a worldview. In some ways, Christianity is the shapeless goo that it expects men to allow themselves to be reduced to in the sense that it is so designed as not to take a stand on any issue that can be legitimate questioned. It seeks to be there and not there at the same time, and in the minds of the believer, it succeeds in this chameleonic ideal.

There are, of course, two possibilities which Harrison has evidently neither considered nor preempted in his advisories, which are:

  1. ...that what the Christian apologist may call "a misunderstanding of true Christianity" may in fact be a point of criticism which slashes off all non-essentials and exposes the roots of Christianity's fundamental errors. This is what an Objectivist approach to atheology can be counted on to provide in pointing out a religious view’s dependence on the primacy of consciousness.
  2. …that the fact that Christian theism is pliant enough within itself to give its defenders the confidence to claim that any criticism made against it can be turned away from it, finds its cause in the arbitrariness of theistic metaphysics. Indeed, an idea or set of ideas which is committed to the fallacy of pure self-reference at its very root has already abandoned all reference to objective reality in fundamentals, and sensing this its defenders presume to have the ability to re-interpret Christian theism in order to escape legitimate scrutiny, and to argue both sides of a contradiction while offering the distraction of an enticing, palliative veneer.

 Without stopping to consider any of this, Harrison continues: 

And so we examine the cogency of each side's theory within the respective worldviews.

While on the surface such a strategy may seem rationally plausible. However, Harrison has already shown that if the opposing side raises any objections to Christianity, those objections reduce to misunderstanding, or are simply “not legitimate objections within the Christian worldview.” Moreover, on deeper penetration such a policy implies that both worldviews in question are restricted to purely self-referential criteria, and thus void of some external standard to provide their ultimate reference point. In the case of Objectivism, that reference point is reality, the realm of existence, the realm of fact, which is something external to the mind developing its worldview. In contrast to this, religious belief has been shown to be built on purely self-referential fundamentals, fundamentals which have no objective reference to reality. [24]

By eliminating the need for an objective point of reference on which to base one's worldview, one declares that rational standards are fundamentally important and that anything but Man's reason is important. Thus, his emotions, his whims, his imagination, his concrete-bound and cognition-disabling fantasies are elevated above his objectivity, and logic, as a method of form only and void of an objective basis, is free to be enlisted to effect some pretense of order and rationality. Hence, as we saw above in Bahnsen's endorsement of Proverbs 1:7, "The fear of God is the beginning of knowledge." In other words, knowledge is not rooted in reason, but in emotion, an emotion which is overwhelming and which paralyzes Man's very courage to assert his mind as independent of others.

Harrison asserts: 

The Christian, within the Christian worldview, can account for rationality, logic, science, morality, etc., because we are thinking God's thoughts after Him, and thus conforming to reality. The unbeliever, since his worldview does not conform to reality (i.e., denies God) cannot account for any of these things.

Here the apologist explicitly acknowledges the presuppositionalist inclination to hijacking "rationality, logic, science, morality, etc." as belonging to its mystical premises, even though the bible nowhere speaks of rationality, logic, or science, and nowhere provides a principled understanding of morality. He acknowledges that a valid worldview should conform to reality, but he equates reality with God. Yet on every philosophical essential, as we have seen, Christian theism rejects objective reality explicitly and man's means of identifying it, which is reason. Thus statements as the one here are patently and irremediably false.

This is not to say that any non-Christian or non-theistic worldview is consistent with objective reality and rationality. Indeed, atheism as such is a negative and has meaning only in regard to god-belief; it is not its own worldview. That one is an atheist only tells us what he does not believe or affirm, and leaves completely open what he does believe and the convictions he may hold and advocate. This is why man has such a profound need for Objectivism, for it is the only philosophy which begins explicitly with objective reality and never departs from it.

Harrison displays the presumptuous nature of the presuppositional approach to apologetics: 

And so, in a nut shell, the apologist engages in an internal critique of the opposing worldview in order to demonstrate that it is arbitrary (moral relativism, for instance), inconsistent with itself (he knows through observation, but cannot observe that observation is the way to know), and lacks the preconditions for knowing anything at all (he has no basis for the existence of universal abstract entities like logic and morality).

Notice that this procedure assumes that the opposing worldview in question is in fact arbitrary; it presupposes that opposing positions are wrong, and sets out to “prove” this, even if it involves recourse to stock refutations of a position that is not affirmed by the opposing worldview (such as moral relativism). This apologetic approach tends to inculcate in its practitioners a false sense of security through its reliance on a wide assortment of such useless tactics. On that note, however, how does Christian theism guard its serious adherents from the very moral relativism to which it accuses non-Christian philosophies commit their adherents? How does the Christian principle "love thy neighbor as thyself" ensure moral objectivity? Such a principle could never ensure moral objectivity, for it constitutes a directive to ignore what one might know about the character of another and to value him regardless of that person's character. How can an upstanding, moral individual, an individual who neither expects or accepts the unearned, either in value or in guilt, value those who do? Such a principle is precisely what guarantees the kind of moral relativism which can destroy a culture when practiced wholesale by an entire community.

Like other apologists for Christianity, Harrison ignores such details, details which are requisite to the Christian paradigm itself. What matters is not the internal incoherence of Christianity itself, but the mastery of manipulating non-believers: 

We can then take anything which seems to be important to the unbeliever and demonstrate to him that if his own worldview were true, his belief would be incoherent and/or meaningless. As Bahnsen says, "In short, the transcendental critique of unbelieving worldviews aims to show that, given their presuppositions, there could be no knowledge in any field whatsoever--that it would be impossible to find meaning or intelligibility in anything at all."

By Bahnsen's own acknowledgment, presuppositionalism - or, the "transcendental critique" - as such is not geared toward an objective analysis of opposing worldviews (as I have provided in regard to Christianity above), but to assaulting the minds of non-believers so that they accept the apologists stolen concepts unwittingly, through straw-manning non-believing philosophies, complex questions, leading questions, alleging neglected onuses, hijacking legitimate philosophical issues and retrofitting them with questionable premises, and inscribing logical reversals. The twists and turns of the presuppositionalist's intellectual meandering are indeed difficult to follow at first blush. But with some principled scrutiny and devoted attention span, that meandering path can be identified and inoculated for intellectual predators.

Then Harrison indicates presuppositionalism’s readiness to backpedal to its built-in disclaimers, which are designed to anticipate objections raised in response to obvious contradictions that loiter in its deeper core:

Note that this is not to say that unbelievers do not reason or communicate or engage in science. It does say that when they do so, they are borrowing from the Christian worldview, which only makes sense, regardless of what they might say, the Bible says that they actually do know God.

If "makes sense" is a measure of a worldview's validity (and if by "makes sense" one means "objectively comprehensible"), then I can see no alternative than to reject Christian theism as an over-burdened, reversal-laden, contradiction-saturated collection of myth and overindulged nonsense. Such is the invention of misguided minds, intellectually stranded by stolen concepts and conceptually marooned by frozen abstractions. I am entirely convinced that every argument for God's existence which I have reviewed and examined is deeply fallacious, and that the ultimate flaw at the root of all such arguments is the same error: stolen concepts necessitating pure self-reference, package-deals socked with reverse packaging. The presuppositional apologetic, one of the more philosophically developed forms of religious apologetics, offers undeniable evidence for my findings.

Like a stupefied boy in blindfolds swinging a bat at an unmovable, impenetrable piñata, the presuppositionalist fails to acquire clear aim at rational philosophy, for he must assume the validity of its very premises before he can even reach for his bat. And if that bat should strike any hits, it is his own stolen concepts which those hits ultimately reveal, and consequently he will lose his intellectual balance and flee to the arbitrariness enshrined by his god-belief. This is why so many presuppositionalists abandon debate unless they believe they have their opponent outnumbered.

The inherent arbitrariness of the apologist’s god-belief may take the form of a claim to revelation (i.e., that he has possession of all knowledge already), or of alleged "mysteries" to which only "the chosen" have access. This access must be given to man deliberately, it is held, for man can do nothing on his own, let alone obtain the truth. (Man was, of course, created in this perfect creator’s image.) Nor can the knowledge of the divine nor the means by which it is allegedly acquired be discovered or earned by man through his own effort, cognitive or otherwise. Its purpose is to enable evasion and to rationalize away the tracks leading to those evasions.

Notice how profoundly the mysticism of post-biblical Christianity figures in presuppositionalism’s sense of man’s existence: 

And it is that triune God of the Bible that is behind all of man's experiences and intellectual efforts. And so the Presuppositional Apologetic recognizes that the critic of Christianity has been secretly presupposing the truth of the faith even as he argues against it.

Statements like these are found throughout presuppositionalist rhetoric. They are deliberately presumptuous and calculated to generate heat, not light. The root of such statements is the primacy of consciousness view of reality and nature. To make sense of our "experiences and intellectual efforts," presuppositionalists point out, we must assume the uniformity of nature and the laws of logic, which is not contested by Objectivism. However, to assume the uniformity of nature and the laws of logic, argue presuppositionalists, one must assume the existence of the "triune God of the Bible," since, as some presuppositionalists might say, God, as creator and sustainer of the universe, is the agency responsible for the uniformity of nature and the validity of logic. Thus, according to this view, to employ logic and to assume the uniformity of nature, one is necessarily and "secretly presupposing the truth of the faith even as he argues against it."

I argue that this view is the result of a fundamental derailment of knowledge from its hierarchical order, resulting in a reversal of metaphysical priorities, and of a fundamentally false view of reality altogether.

 Harrison continues:

As Bahnsen has said, it is like a person arguing that air does not exist, all the while breathing air as a precondition for his ability to argue. In conclusion, the only "proof" of Christianity is the impossibility of the contrary.

Man denying air while breathing it is not at all analogous to man using his own mind (which he introspectively can know exists) while recognizing that fictional beings are in fact fictional. And Harrison has offered no reason why we should suspect that his god is something other than a fictional character. But what Harrison describes here is most likely the manner that one's own stolen concepts appear to those who accept them. For those who do accept stolen concepts of such arbitrary nature as this are apt to consider them so rudimentary that they will tend to treat them as fundamentally non-negotiable and impassible. It is as simple as the French philosopher Voltaire quipped, "If God did not exist, it would be necessary to invent him." Proving the alleged truth of the arbitrary by appealing to the "impossibility of the contrary" is an easy out for the apologist. It is an attempt to do all of one's illegitimate intellectual heavy-lifting in one quick grasp-and-jerk action, pressing the non-existent above one's own head in a single motion. In consists of a morass of bald assertions which resist assembly into any identifiable course of inference substantiating any of the apologist’s god-belief claims, but this does not stop Harrison from his triumphant sloganeering:

Unless the Christian position is presupposed, at a conscious or unconscious level, there is no possibility for proving anything.

In other words, unless the truth of the Christian's god-belief claims are presupposed to begin with, there is no possibility for proving them. But if these claims are presupposed as true to begin with, then all effort to prove them would end up begging the question. While most non-believers (and indeed many believers as well) immediately recognize the invalidity of presuppositionalism, presuppositionalists themselves insist that all worldviews end up begging the question, including non-theistic worldviews, since circular reasoning, they believe, is unavoidable for man. The erroneous nature of this position is dealt with in numerous essays posted at this site. [25]

As is typical with this strain of religious apologetics, Harrison wants to push the non-believer into the hard corner of a difficult choice, as if it were simply a matter of choosing that Christianity were true or false. He writes:

When it is all said and done, the unbeliever will have two options:

      1. Acknowledge the truth, or
      2. Reject rationality

Many will choose to do just that, although they will deny that is what they are doing. After all, proving is not the same as persuading. But in any case, the apologetic purpose will have been fulfilled. The hope within us will have been defended within the biblical framework.

Of course, thinkers generally do not want to go on record as rejecting rationality. Harrison realizes this, and uses this to frontload his false dichotomy with the predisposition it seeks to exploit. By "acknowledge the truth," Harrison really means accept the claims of Christianity as if they were in fact true. Rejecting Christianity thus entails rejecting rationality. So if one wants to "acknowledge the truth" and embrace rationality, on Harrison's terms he would have to accept everything that Christianity claims as truth, even if he's not in a position to know whether its claims are true or not. It's all part of a bundled package that one is expected to accept in one lumpsum. [26]  

The fundamental error supporting this gimmick, however, is that it overlooks the fact that the basis of rationality is the primacy of existence, the very principle which Christian god-belief thwarts by its adherence to the primacy of consciousness view of reality. Rationality does not assume that consciousness holds metaphysical primacy over its objects: it does not assume that consciousness has the power to dictate the outcomes of inquiries about reality, inferences from facts, scientifically conducted experiments; that the world of objects conforms to the content of consciousness, that wishing does not make reality what it is. On the contrary, rationality assumes that the role of consciousness is to perceive, discover and identify what exists and what is real. But Christianity is certainly not consistent with this fundamental principle. It enshrines the notion of a universe-creating, reality-ruling consciousness to whose content everything directly and immediately conforms. It created the universe by an act of "will" and controls every event that takes place in the world throughout history by means of its "plan." This entire conception clearly assumes the ontological priority of consciousness over its objects.


NOTES
_____________________________________

[1] Taken from the anonymous online article Natural Theology, associated with the Theology on the Web site, a source demonstrably sympathetic to Christian theism.

[2] Quoted from Bahnsen's short essay Van Til's 'Presuppositionalism'.

[3] Quoted from Mr. Anderson's post to the Van Til Discussion list, dated September 19, 1998, titled Good Reasons.

[4] For elaboration on this matter, see my article God and Pure Self-Reference, in my Letters to a Young Atheologist series.

[5] Quoted from Bahnsen's short article Autonomy is No Ladder to Christ's Supreme Authority.

[6] "The Objectivist Ethics," The Virtue of Selfishness, (New York: Signet, 1964), pp. 20-21.

[7] Atlas Shrugged, p. 943.

[8] Quoted in Leonard Peikoff's The Ominous Parallels, (New York: Meridian, 1993), p. 33.

[9] The apologist above writes that "the unbeliever cannot reason autonomously." It is unlikely that those who believe that unbelievers "cannot reason autonomously" will turn around and claim that believers do reason autonomously, if by "autonomous" the believer means "without guidance and/or approval of God's will and/or law." For the believer naturally claims that his "thought" is in "accordance" with God's will and/or law, lest he be deemed by his own worldview to have fallen from grace and into sin, which would soil his credibility from a perspective internal to Christianity. (Indeed, there's strong reason for non-believer's to question the believer's credibility to begin with, which I will detail in an upcoming essay titled "Considering the Source." Paul's own statement in Romans 3:4 - "let God be true, but every man a liar." If the apologist is a man, and it is the case that every man is a liar, then the apologist himself is a liar. If the apologist claims that he does not speak for himself, but on behalf of "God's truth," he still does not escape the lack of credibility to which the Bible itself condemns him.)

[10] Cf. the claim that matter as such is "contingent"; upon what is matter said to be contingent? Upon God, i.e., upon an alleged form of consciousness.

[11] Cited from Bahnsen's short essay Van Til's 'Presuppositionalism'. "Christ," according to Christians, is God, hence "Christianity" (internal confusions resulting from the doctrine of the trinity and its non-cognitive fallout notwithstanding). Readers are invited to examine my critique of this short essay.

[12] "Philosophy: Who Needs It," Philosophy: Who Needs It, (New York: Signet, 1984), p. 7.

[13] For further development of how the claim "God exists" is self-contradicting, see my critique of Eric Smallwood's apologetic and The Contradiction of Theism, an upcoming installment in my Letters to a Young Atheologist series.

[14] A good example of this emphasis will be seen in Mark McConnell’s 7 July 2000 message to the Van Til list (archived here), in which the apologist questions the non-believer's ability to achieve cognitive certainty when he "is not aware of any principle by which he can know where the cosmos came from." In other words, one's notions about the origin of the cosmos, according to this view, should hold primacy over principles which are derived from the perceptually self-evident facts of reality. Obviously this course of inquiry can be extended ad nauseum in an effort to smoke out the inability to answer, which is the chief aim here. Should one point to something beyond “the cosmos” as the source “where the cosmos came from,” one can easily ask where that source came from, and so on. This course of apologetic inquiry is easily lent to an infinite regress. The goal here is not to enlighten the mind with legitimate knowledge, but to create doubt in the minds of one’s audience and to exploit that doubt in an effort to beat those minds to a shapeless pulp.

Another example of how many apologists emphasize the primacy of alleged history over the present and verifiable, perceptually self-evident facts of reality, is seen in the case of scrutinizing a non-believer's rejection of the Christian doctrine of miracles. Non-believers will often point out the absurdity of the doctrine of miracles by rightly arguing that such a doctrine contradicts the facts of reality (since 'miracle' is a violation of the law of identity). Rather than arguing positively on behalf of the alleged instances of miracles in the attempt to prove that indeed a miracle has happened as he claims, the apologist insists that the non-believer justify his rejection of the allegation of the miraculous, and perhaps even prove that the alleged miracle(s) in question did not happen. In such a way, the apologist is often inclined to argue negatively - i.e., to call into question one's rejection of Christianity, and to substitute this negative kind of assault on non-believers for a positive substantiation and justification of his god-belief claims.

[15] It should also be noted that it is the direct opposite which holds true in the relationship between philosophy and history. For history as such does not inform a comprehensive view of life, which is the task of philosophy, which Christian theism attempts to do by retroactive inference. In sharp contrast to this, Objectivism recognizes that philosophy, more than any other factor, dictates and directs the course of human history. (See Ayn Rand, For the New Intellectual, p. 28; Philosophy: Who Needs It, p. 200; et al.) Since history is the result of ideas put into action on both local and large scales, we would be wise to recognize the influence of a particular philosophical viewpoint on the historical development (or stagnation) of a culture, rather than expect particular historic events to substitute for philosophical principles. In this context, Christian theism as a candidate for philosophy commits a reversal of colossal proportions.

[16] For articles on Objectivism, the Philosophy of Reason, see my Objectivist links page.

[17] Indeed, some religious apologists hold that man is incapable of objectivity. One such believer, himself a Christian, took the opportunity to tell me so. See my correspondence An Aborted Rise to Challenge for my response to this individual.

[18] For further reading on the absolute nature of Objectivist morality, I strongly suggest Ayn Rand's brilliant and original essay, "The Objectivist Ethics," in her book The Virtue of Selfishness.

[19] Ayn Rand, Atlas Shrugged, p. 957.

[20] Volition as Cognitive Self-Regulation, (Oceanside, CA: Second Renaissance Books, 1991), p. 8.

[21] Harry Binswanger, "The Metaphysics of Consciousness," Tape 3, Side A.

[22] Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology, p. 4.

[23] “Atheists with Attitude,” The New Yorker, May 21, 2007.

[24] Again, see particularly my letter God and Pure Self-Reference for a fuller exposition of the purely self-referential foundations of god-belief.

[25] For instance, see my correspondence Presuppositionalist Circularities, which documents one leading presuppositionalist's own admission that his system relies on circular fallacy. See also TAG and the Fallacy of the Stolen Concept. Or, suppose someone came up to you and suggested that, “unless the [truth of Alice in Wonderland] is presupposed, at a conscious or unconscious level, there is no possibility for proving anything.” How is the presuppositionalist position essentially different from this?

[26] Notice with Christianity that we are not expected to accept, for instance, that Jesus was baptized by John the Baptist but not born of a virgin, or that he lead a preaching ministry in and about Jerusalem in the first century, but neither performed miracles nor effected miraculous cures. Although we were not there to witness the miracles we read about in the gospels, we're supposed to believe that Jesus performed them just as the gospel stories describe them. A true believer, then, is one who affirms the entirety of a religion's dogmas indiscriminately; he does not accept only that which might reasonably seem plausible and reject that which is clearly absurd. In the mind of the believer, there is no distinction between plausibility and absurdity when it comes to the elements of his religious confession.

 

Copyright © by Anton Thorn 2000, 2002, 2004, 2007. All rights reserved.

[Back to the Top]

[Back to Thorn's Morgue]

[Back to Anton Thorn's Main Page]