Induction and Presuppositional Apologetics:
An Examination of Andy Walker's Argument

by Anton Thorn

 

For ease of user navigation, this essay is divided up into the following sections:

Introduction
Background
Preliminary Apologetic Claims
The Essentials of Induction: Mr. Walker's Argument
Grounding Induction
The "Rational Ingredients" of Induction
The Theist's Real Agenda
Can We Expect Honesty from the Apologist?
Conclusion

  

Introduction:

By now you have hopefully read my Introductory Critique of Presuppositionalism. In that piece I examine the fundamentals of presuppositionalist apologetics according to at least one spokesman's understanding of its schemes. My findings were basically that presuppositionalism:

The irony providing the backdrop of these findings is the fact that, as an apologetic method, presuppositionalism does nothing to prove the claim that a god exists, Christian or otherwise, a minimal expectation for an argumentative scheme which postures itself as championing "an argument for the existence of God." [1] Whether or not this is a failure of depends on whether or not its exponents consider such a proof to be one of presuppositionalism's goals (and it's certainly not always clear that they do). And even if presuppositionalists allow that their apologetic is not intended to prove the existence of the Christian god, this recognition alone does not seem sufficient to keep them from carrying on as if they had such a proof.

Now that we have some idea of the nature of presuppositionalist apologetics, we are ready to examine it in action. And in this series I examine three apologists' efforts to engage a non-believer with the presuppositionalist approach, thus exposing its weaknesses and errors for the observing audience. Among many other discoveries I have made, I will show that presuppositionalism cannot escape its commitment to the fallacy of the stolen concept at its foundations, to which I hold that all theistic doctrines owe their basis.

The analysis which follows finds its source in an exchange of e-mail posts to the Van Til Discussion list, which provides a forum for dialogue between seasoned presuppositionalist apologists and their budding protégés. In late April, 2000, a non-believer entered the discussion asking a number of questions with the hope of gaining a wider understanding of presuppositionalism and its rhetorical accoutrements. As can be expected, a number of the regular participants of the Van Til list piped in with their responses to the questions raised by this self-described skeptic, referred to in my analyses by his name Brian. In the present paper I shall analyze the arguments and remarks of one of those participants, Mr. Andy Walker, whose original post to the Van Til list can be found at the following link:

http://www.ccir.ed.ac.uk/~jad/vantil-list/archive-May-2000/msg00011.html

Quotations attributed to Mr. Walker will refer to this post, unless otherwise noted.

 

Background:

One of the primary focuses of presuppositionalist "thought" is found in the area of classical philosophical issues, such as universals and induction, with which many modern philosophers have struggled in futile effort. In regard to these "problems," exponents of presuppositionalism make the bold claim that their version of Christianity supplies all the answers needed finally to resolve them. In regard to induction, which is the primary focus of Mr. Walker's apologetic in the above-referenced post, and consequently of my proceeding analysis, philosopher Michael Martin offers the following recognition in this respect:

Christian apologists like [Greg] Bahnsen who appeal to [the "transcendental argument for the existence of God"] acknowledge their debt to David Hume, the eighteenth century Scottish skeptic, and Bertrand Russell, one of the twentieth century's most famous philosophers. Both thinkers raised skeptical questions about induction. Bahnsen's strategy was to take these seriously and then try to show that belief in the Christian God could dispel them. Unfortunately, he exhibited no awareness of the philosophical arguments that have challenged inductive skepticism in general and Hume's and Russell's versions of it in particular. [2]

Essentially, the presuppositionalist apologetic holds that one is not "justified" to assume the validity of the pre-conditions of induction without also assuming the existence of the Christian God as the agent responsible for the reality of those pre-conditions.

For instance, apologist Sean Choi claims that "Although athe*ists* believe and act like real laws of nature exists, their athe*ism* provides no rational justification for their belief." [3] On the face of such a claim, already we can detect an allegation of the neglected onus, which is a fallacy identified in my essay on fallacies. According to my essay, this fallacy

occurs when an individual charges that his opponent's position does not sufficiently deal with an obligation that has not been shown to properly belong to the opponent's position… As such, it constitutes an illegitimate attempt to discredit a position by asserting a charge that such a position does not sufficiently deal with an issue that does not legitimately belong to it.

Atheism is the negation of god-belief, and as such makes no positive philosophical claims. By extension, atheism asserts no positive view of metaphysics, epistemology or ethics, and therefore bears no obligation to inform a view on induction. To hold atheism as such responsible for providing solutions to philosophical quagmires, and then attack it when it does not satisfy this alleged obligation, is, in my view, fallacious. Such attempts to discredit non-belief are the result of a poor and prejudiced understanding of the concepts involved.

However, this does not relieve an individual from the necessity of using his mind and of defining the proper means of cognition. The science which provides the proper means of cognition, as well as the principles which give man's cognition its foundation, is philosophy. According to Objectivism, philosophy is indispensable to man's life. I quote Ayn Rand:

Philosophy studies the fundamental nature of existence, of man, and of man's relationship to existence. As against the special sciences, which deal only with particular aspects, philosophy deals with those aspects of the universe which pertain to everything that exists. In the realm of cognition, the special sciences are the trees, but philosophy is the soil which makes the forest possible. [4]

Philosophy is the science that studies the fundamental aspects of the nature of existence. The task of philosophy is to provide man with a comprehensive view of life. This view serves as a base, a frame of reference, for all his actions, mental or physical, psychological or existential. This view tells him the nature of the universe with which he has to deal (metaphysics); the means by which he is to deal with it, i.e., the means of acquiring knowledge (epistemology); the standards by which he is to choose his goals and values, in regard to his own life and character (ethics) - and in regard to society (politics); the means of concretizing this view is given to him by esthetics. [5]

Consequently, while I maintain that atheism per se does not inform a view of the fundamental nature of existence - and consequently is not obliged to "provide a rational justification" for one's views on the fundamental nature of existence, one's particular philosophical ideas, whether they are implicitly or explicitly held, do inform such a view. Consequently, it is wrongheaded to hold atheism as such accountable for such a justification.

Thus, to pursue Mr. Choi's question, "Can the atheist, *within his metaphysical assumptions*, provide a rational justification for the inductive principle?" it is necessary to ask: "What are a given atheist's metaphysical assumptions?" Are these assumptions held implicitly, or explicitly? What is the basis of these assumptions? Are there presumptions which these assumptions themselves presuppose? What ultimately lies at the bedrock of a given atheist's cognition? Essentially, what is his starting point?

These are all valid questions for sure, but one atheist can hardly answer such questions for another, nor should a theist presume to fill in these blanks for all atheists. For one atheist, while dispensing with god-belief, may assert that nothing about the universe can be known with any certainty (cf. skepticism), while another may assert an alternate view that certainty is not only possible to man, but that it is innate or inborn, that man is born with some knowledge automatically (cf. rationalism). Such views enter the realm of actual philosophical positions, and suggest what one does believe or accept to be the case as opposed to the negative nature of atheism proper, which only tells us what one does not believe. Arguably, one can hold to either of these positions while still rejecting the harrowing defects of god-belief.

For the Objectivist, however, neither of these positions will do. Objectivism holds that man is capable of achieving certainty in his pursuit of knowledge, and thus rejects hard-boiled skepticism. But Objectivism also holds that man must acquire certainty through his perceptual contact with reality, including the certainty of his starting points, that man requires a means which enables him to acquire knowledge (which is called reason), and thus rejects rationalism. And since Objectivism embraces rationality consistently in all its fundamentals and doctrines, it also rejects the mysticism of god-belief. [6]

However, from what I've gathered from my attendance to their literature, these facts and distinctions are not at all what presuppositionalists tend to incorporate into their argument schemes. Instead, their argument is that a whole and proper view of induction cannot be complete without the inclusion of their particular Christian god-belief in the presuppositional foundations of induction, since, they hold, the universe is the creation of the Christian God of the Bible, and that any predication (that is, affirming truths) taking place within it at least implicitly acknowledges this to be the case. It is certain aspects of this claim and its supporting arguments which I examine in the following analysis.

 

Preliminary apologetic claims:

Mr. Walker holds that "all arguments for ultimate authority end up 'begging the question.'" While this indeed holds to varying degree within the framework of all philosophical viewpoints built on the primacy of consciousness view of reality, it is irrelevant to Objectivism because Objectivism does not base its principles and doctrines on the appeal to personal authority, but on the direct appeal to reality via perception. Where the religionist ultimately argues "You better believe what we claim, or else!" - which is essentially an ad baculum [7], the only corresponding Objectivist position would be, "Ignore reality at your own peril."

Neither does Objectivism confuse its starting point with the conclusion of prior argumentation, as presuppositionalism tends to do. [8] Objectivism neither holds nor treats the axioms (i.e., its starting point) as conclusions following from prior premises. The presuppositionalist method, as an indicator of broader philosophical integration (or disintegration), at best stumbles carelessly in a groping manner with regard to the objective, hierarchical nature of knowledge. This has more to do with the doctrines which presuppositionalism is intended to defend, than with the apologetic system itself, which simply inherits and mirrors those doctrines' flaws. [9]

But even if we grant Mr. Walker's premises for argument's sake, how does he establish that "All arguments for ultimate authority end up 'begging the question'"? Certainly even the presuppositionalist must admit that this is a broad generalization which Mr. Walker asserts, but for which he offers no support, at least in his post, nor does he cite a source which offers such support. If he were to put forth an argument to support this, what would it be? Or, perhaps he just parrots this claim from its sources as if its truth were self-evident or uncontroversial.

But even before he should put forth a supporting argument for this generalization which he applies universally (including to his own schemes), he should explain what he means by "ultimate authority" and what presumptions this notion has (i.e., he should define his own terms).

For instance, does Mr. Walker presume that an "ultimate authority" is a form of consciousness distinct from his own? If so, by what authority does he presume this? And, if so, by what authority does this consciousness' identification of reality proceed? And on what authority does this consciousness take its own conclusions to be authoritative (assuming it can)? By its own authority? This is where the religionist's own circularities become more vicious and interminably regressive. [10]

What is important is that Mr. Walker is willing to admit that he begs the question in attempting to establish his conclusions. Commitment to fallacy is just that: a commitment to cognitive error. How does Mr. Walker expect arguments to succeed when they can only proceed on the commitment to fallacy? Blank out.

Mr. Walker tries to clarify his point when he writes, "The question is not whether one 'begs the question', but whether or not one's ultimate foundations can provide an adequate explanation for all that we assume to be true of the universe." But this continues his admission that question-begging is indeed a necessary part of his worldview and apologetic. This is his error, not the non-believer's. Declaring one's own commitment to circularity and expecting the non-believer to match fallacy for fallacy - presumably by necessity - are counterproductive to his expressed goal of providing a convincing argument or "adequate explanation," but it is no surprise given the stolen concepts upon which his view is internally dependent.

As for providing "an adequate explanation for all that we assume to be true of the universe," one merely needs to recognize explicitly the fact that existence exists and its corollaries. [11] Even the apologist must recognize and employ this fact, although he does so only implicitly, and then only to the expedience of his pet god-belief conclusions (i.e., non-objectively). To be sure, it is to the degree that he does identify this fact that he expects a form of consciousness to "account for" it metaphysically. For presuppositionalists, the primacy of consciousness view of reality, which is false, is fundamental to his god-belief program. Thus, we see that not only does Mr. Walker openly commit himself to circular reasoning in the establishment of his view, which he does admit, his entire view of reality is built on the fallacy of the stolen concept, which he likely does not recognize.

One wonders precisely what may constitute Mr. Walker's standards for adequacy in explanation when he affirms that an explanation (i.e., appealing to "God") reached by circular argument achieves this adequacy. Adequacy according to what standard? Certainly this standard cannot be reason, for the reasonable does not knowingly proceed on the basis of admitted fallacy.

The apologist challenges the non-believer to "provide an adequate explanation" or to "account for" the uniformity of nature. But the uniformity which we discover in nature is simply the extension of the fact that existence exists, and its corollary - the fact that existence is identity - to everything which exists. The apologist expects the non-believer to "justify" his presumption of these facts, which are perceptually available to both believers and non-believers, which means: the non-believer cannot assume the law of identity in order to "prove" that nature is uniform (without begging the question). But why should anyone want to try to "prove" that nature is uniform, particularly when this fact is entailed axiomatically (i.e., corollary to axiomatic concepts)?

The apologist hopes that the non-believer will take the bait, so to say, and attempt such a "justification" without appealing to the perceptually self-evident, and thus trap himself into begging the question (and with this the apologist will presume to "score" a debating point in favor of theism). But since 'proof' presupposes identity (i.e., that A is A) and thus this law cannot be subject to proof, we must look prior to proofs, to one's starting points, to the axioms which anchor the basis of all cognition. For the Objectivist, these starting points are existence, identity and consciousness. [12]

So the apologist not only bears the onus of demonstrating the worthiness of any alleged starting point he claims to ground his view of reality and knowledge (Is it irreducible? Is it fundamental? How is he aware of it? etc.), he also bears the onus of proving the existence of his alleged God, which so far he has not done. And suppose he could prove the existence of God, what then? The consequences for the apologist would not be in favor for the doctrines he is peddling; instead, the very possibility of a proof of God's existence would spell disaster for his agenda. As one prominent Objectivist notes,

It has often been noted that a proof of God would be fatal to religion: a god susceptible of proof would have to be finite and limited; He would be one entity among others within the universe, not a mystic omnipotence transcending science and reality. What nourishes the spirit of religion is not proof, but faith, i.e., the undercutting of man's mind. [13]

If one could prove the existence of God, then this knowledge would be available to all men, since it would no longer be a matter of faith, but a matter of reason. But if the existence of God were provable and now a matter of reason rather than faith, then where would that put Christian theism as a philosophy with all its appeals to mystery and mysticism? How could Christian doctrine be considered a matter of revelation if one could validly argue for its conclusions? Where would a legitimate proof of God's existence put the priest? Indeed, a genuine proof of God's existence would radically cripple religion both philosophically and, more importantly, psychologically.

Additionally, and more specifically in regard to the present context of Mr. Walker's argument, if the existence of God were demonstrable through logical proofs, how could the presuppositionalist claim that God is the ground and precondition of induction? Such a position would still be suspicious since our knowledge of God's existence would have to be a derivative of reason (i.e., by inference, not by perceptual self-evidence), and not its "sufficient cause." Thus we have good cause to wonder exactly what the presuppositionalist methodology hopes to accomplish. [14]

Mr. Walker reasons:

You might think,

"Well, if all parties involved in a discussion end up begging the question when appealing to ultimate authorities, doesn't this just end in a stalemate? You have your explanations, I have mine!"

It would if all parties were equally INCAPABLE of providing a rational foundation for ultimate questions. But that is not the case. There isn't a stalemate because the Biblical worldview can provide such a justification for induction, uniformity of nature, the laws of logic, human dignity and objective morality.

Mr. Walker above countered his critic by pointing out instances of begging the question in the latter's critical objections to the transcendental scheme. But now Mr. Walker simply reiterates his position, the very position that is in question, as if he had provided a sealed case for its certainty. Indeed, he has not done this. Repeating a claim does not serve as that claim's rational support. And admitting fallacy (see above) only concedes one's position to self-defeat.

Objectivity can only be possible to man when his philosophical foundations are committed to the facts that existence exists independent of consciousness and that existence holds metaphysical primacy over consciousness [15]; that man has certain needs in order to exist, and that fulfilling those needs does not constitute "sin"; that in order for man to live he cannot resign his mind to commandments and act on the morality of self-sacrifice, but must learn to identify and pursue by his own reasoning those values which make his life possible. [16] All these points are ignored or rejected outright when the apologist points to the mystical as providing the partial or exclusive 'solution' to philosophical issues which man must address in order to live his life. The point of the matter is, that man's epistemic and moral needs are based on and arise from his nature as a living organism, as Objectivism recognizes, not on alleged historical events, as Christianity essentially claims.

And, curiously, to make the claim that we should accept the Christian worldview as true because it can provide a "justification for induction, uniformity of nature, the laws of logic, human dignity and objective morality" is inconsistent with the approach to Christian theism advocated by "master apologist" Greg Bahnsen. Bahnsen writes in his short essay Van Til's 'Presuppositionalism' that God's "word and character are not questionable." This can only mean that believers must accept the claims and teachings of the Bible unquestioningly, regardless of what kind of "sense" it makes to a believer, regardless of whether or not the Christian worldview resolves certain philosophical problems which plague other views.

In informal debates I have asked advocates of presuppositionalism if it is the case that they accept the Bible's claims and teachings unquestioningly, and, after some understandable hesitation, they have affirmed this. This is an extremely uncomfortable - dilemma for the believer to find himself in, for if on the one hand he does not affirm that he accepts the teachings of the Bible unquestioningly, then he must consequently admit that he measures those teachings according to some standard external to the Bible (such as his own reasoning, which is condemned by presuppositionalism as deceitfully "autonomous"), thus compromising his claim to submission to "God's authority" as 'ultimate'. And if he says that he measures the Bible's validity by reference to "the created order," he begs the question, for he assumes the truth of the notion of creation, a staple doctrine of Christianity.

On the other hand, if he does admit that he accepts the teachings of the Bible unquestioningly, as suggested by Bahnsen's remark, then he must admit that he will never be in a position to evaluate the validity of the Bible's claims objectively (i.e., without warranted prejudice), because they must be taken completely for granted from the beginning, regardless of external support (or the lack thereof) and in the absence of rational verification. The Bible is quite a lengthy yarn to be subject to such undiscriminating acceptance, and would require complete intellectual surrender on the part of the believer in order for this claim to actually be considered true.

Mr. Walker's claim that Christian theism alone provides a consistent "justification for induction, uniformity of nature, the laws of logic, human dignity and objective morality" directly conflicts with the view that the teachings of the Bible should be accepted unquestioningly, for now he appeals to some standard which he believes Christian theism can satisfy. This is hardly consistent.

When Mr. Walker asserts that "No other worldview can provide such" a justification, allegedly without begging the question (an error in cognition which he admits his own worldview commits), he offers another unargued claim. Not only does this statement deepen his previously acknowledged commitment to circular reasoning, it takes the form of a universal negative claim which is most likely offered prematurely and smacks of purely dogmatic bias (i.e., he wants it to be the case). The principal question here then becomes: How does he arrive at this conclusion? The theist may respond to the request for proof concluding that "no other worldview than Christian theism can provide a rational justification for induction, uniformity of nature, etc." by pointing out that atheists routinely acknowledge that they are under no obligation to prove negative assertions (such as the assertion "there is no God") and thus presumes that he's off the hook in this regard. Indeed, the atheist is not obligated to do so (especially when it comes to god-belief debates).

However, since many Christian apologists insist that non-believers prove the non-existence of God, they should be willing to attempt to prove their own negative claims in the interest of consistency. If the theist is unwilling to be consistent with his own instances of insistence on obligations for the atheist, he concedes on this point and thus loses credibility (assuming he's achieved any to begin with). After all, if Mr. Walker is so certain that "no other worldview can provide" a rational justification for induction, the uniformity of nature, the laws of logic, etc., can he not at least demonstrate the steps by which he arrived at this view? Or, should he be satisfied by his own unargued positions? Or, perhaps his assertion is a mere representation of untenable wishful thinking?

Now let us turn to the primary topic which concerns us, namely the uniformity of nature and the foundations of induction, so far as they are relevant to Mr. Walker's apologetic.

 

The Essentials of Induction: Mr. Walker's Argument

According to Dr. Peikoff, "an Aristotelian definition of induction [is] the process of reasoning from the observation of concretes or individuals to a general or universal conclusion." [17] What should be apparent is that induction, according to this understanding, begins with observation of "concretes or individuals"; which means: induction begins with our sense perception of entities. This point is extremely important and its pertinence to this discussion cannot be over-emphasized since theistic treatments of induction tend to lose sight of this essential fact quite quickly. (Quite often budding philosophy neophytes speak of induction as dealing with "events" rather than entities. I think this is a big mistake because it tends to emphasize causality - the identity of action - over existence - the identity of entities, which is incoherent.)

With this fundamental point in mind, let us now examine Mr. Walker's argument in regard to induction.

Mr. Walker's presented the following:

The argument is NOT: "A person must profess belief in the Christian God in order to use induction." The argument IS: "A person who does not profess a belief in the Christian God cannot rationally JUSTIFY his/her use of induction without begging the question." Why? Because when a person attempts to justify his/her use of induction they will appeal to induction as the ground of their justification.

The syllogism would look something like this:

(1) Induction assumes an orderly (not absolutely), predictable (not absolutely) universe.

(2) The atheistic (or non-Biblical) worldview cannot ACCOUNT for an orderly, predictable universe.

(3) Therefore, an atheist (or non-Christian) cannot ACCOUNT for induction.

For the atheist to say, "But I DO use induction." is not a rational justification for using it. To say, "Well the universe IS orderly." is not a rational justification for WHY it is orderly.

The atheist COULD say (and often does), "Well, I use induction because it works." But what has he really said? He has simply begged the question.

We are not saying that we shouldn't trust induction or use induction. We are saying that only a Biblical worldview can provide the rational ingredients to make sense out of induction's reliability.

Before I begin my analysis, there are two primary areas of concern which I believe should be pointed out.

First of all, take a look at Mr. Walker's overall argument. What is it trying to prove? Does it attempt to prove the existence of the biblical God? No, it does not. Does it attempt to prove the existence of any god? No, it does not. Does it attempt to prove the validity of the Christian worldview? No, it does not. Instead, its entire focus is negative in nature, intending specifically to discredit non-theism (or non-Christianity), thus leaving the apologist free to assume the validity of his positive mystical claims as if recognition of their truth followed naturally from such negations or from some other, unidentified prior phenomenon. [18] Even if we suppose that Mr. Walker's argument could somehow be shown to be sound, it does not relieve the apologist from the burden of proving his positive existential claims, including specifically the claim that God exists. At best, Mr. Walker's argument, as it stands here, is an argument from ignorance, and at most can only establish the point that atheists and other non-Christians cannot account for induction (whatever that is intended to mean).

Second, to pre-stage my analysis, there is a serious concern which a review of Mr. Walker's premises brings to light, but which are not convincingly answered in favor of his argument. His first premise specifically includes the parenthetical reservation that the orderliness of the universe is not absolute. While not necessary to his argument's overall validity, this parenthetic aside we shall find is problematic for the theist, ironically in regard to the matter of induction itself! Additionally, we will find that his second premise is untrue. If I can demonstrate that there are problems with Mr. Walker's premises, then we have good reason to reject his conclusion. And when we recognize that Mr. Walker's argument, even if it were sound, fails to establish the existence of the Christian God of the Bible, we should also recognize that such arguments, if this is the best argument we are given to support the apologist's claim that God exists, constitute an evasion of his onus to prove his claims.

 

Premise 1: The Non-Absolute Orderliness of the Universe

(Although this point is not critical to either the validity or the goal of Mr. Walker's argument, I think it deserves special mention in my analysis particularly because of its devastating implications for Christian epistemology in general, and induction in particular, which is of central importance to the present discussion.)

In clarifying his argument, Mr. Walker argues essentially that one must profess belief in - or at least acknowledge the alleged existence of - the Christian God of the Bible in order to "rationally JUSTIFY his/her use of induction without begging the question" (even though above he had stated that "all arguments for ultimate authority end up 'begging the question'"). Certainly, given the influence of the empiricist [19] and rationalist schools of philosophy in today's academia (both of which Objectivism considers to be invalid philosophical approaches), it is not difficult to see why some would retreat to the vacuous abyss of mysticism as an answer to fundamental philosophical problems which have historically plagued those schools. And in addition to this precarious leaning towards mysticism, we see already in Mr. Walker's first paragraph hints of the temptation to argue from silence for the supposed truth of Christian theism. For his argument suggests the general shape that, if non-believers beg the question in their attempt to justify induction, then Christian theism must be true as if by default. But such a conclusion obviously does not follow.

His first premise reads: "Induction assumes an orderly (not absolutely), predictable (not absolutely) universe."

Notice his parenthetical reservations here: Induction assumes an orderly universe, but this orderliness is not absolute. Consequently, if this orderliness is not absolute, then one's ability to predict its events will consequently be non-absolute as well, as Mr. Walker mentions. Thus, presumably, the same cause may not have the same effect in two or more identical instances. No doubt, being a theist of the Christian tradition, which incorporates into its doctrines the assertion that miracles are a reality, Mr. Walker qualifies this orderliness as not absolute in order to leave room to posit divinely inspired revisions of reality (i.e., existence, identity, causality, etc.), and thus allow any elasticity which his dogmatic commitments or argumentative convenience may require him to defend in the future (such as in the case of defending the gospel story of the resurrection).

However, this in and of itself - the positing of a non-absolutely orderly universe - may pose a potential problem for apologists bent on formulating water-tight arguments for their particular brand of theism. For, particularly in Christianity, God is said to be both absolute and perfect. But should we suppose that the non-absolute and the imperfect should find their ultimate source in an absolute and perfect being? This and similar problems have plagued theologians and philosophers alike, leading eventually to the formulation of the classic atheological argument from evil for the incoherence of such god-belief.

Mr. Walker later emphasizes this in his message when he states, "The Christian worldview does not assume ABSOLUTE uniformity and orderliness." But does not Christian theism assume that the "created realm" [sic] is uniformly subject to God's will? And if so, is this uniform subjection to God's will not also absolute? Or, are some things more subject to God's will, while other things are less subject to his will?

Assuredly, the presuppositionalist, in all his posturing about how one might "account for" the uniformity of nature, must leave space for the miraculous antics which Christianity ascribes to the supernatural. Thus, nature is not absolutely uniform, according to presuppositionalism, because this view would prove problematic later when the apologist expects us to accept his claims of miracle events. This loophole which the apologist deliberately builds into his schemes will ultimately lead to the apologist's own total skepticism in the realm of thought about the world. [20]

According to Objectivism, contrary to the unnecessary qualification suggested by Mr. Walker's premise, the universe is absolutely orderly in the sense that wherever existence exists, that which exists has identity. This truth is implicit in the Objectivist axioms, which must be assumed even if one intends to question, ignore or attack them. The universe is defined by Objectivism as the totality of existence; should something exist, it must be something and it must be part of the universe by definition. [21] Objectivism holds consequently that the idea of something existing outside the universe is incoherent and indefensible, given the validity of this definition. Objectivism does not make allowance for any exceptions to the applicability of the law of identity to the things which exist, which is precisely what Mr. Walker's parenthetical reservations intend to supply. In fact, Objectivism recognizes that induction would be futile if there were unpredictable deviations from the law of identity reflecting the reservations for which a theistic treatment of induction would have to allow.

Apart from these parenthetical reservations, I see no problem with the premise that induction assumes an orderly universe. There is, however, no need to compromise the assumed orderliness of the universe, since all exemptions from this orderliness and all violations of the law of identity are deemed arbitrary by Objectivism and only serve to destroy the reliability of induction. Contradictions do not exist, and consequently there is no need to make allowance for contradictions in one's theory of induction.

 

Premise 2: Accounting for "Account for"

When presented with an argument like Mr. Walker's, we must ask what is meant by the crucial term "account for," which is a staple of presuppositional rhetoric, and which appears in both the second premise and the conclusion of Mr. Walker's argument. Does "account for" mean formulate a comprehensive explanation? Does "account for" mean to denude prior assumptions of their unarticulated premises? Does this term mean "reduce to essentials" or "unpack loaded presumptions"? Or, could the request to 'account for' X be a challenge to identify the (alleged or assumed) causal chain responsible for the actuality, or even the mere possibility, of X? Apologist Robinson Mitchell has stated that this recurring term "means a logical explanation from an a priori foundation so that the principle accounted for is seen as reliable knowledge. Account is logical proof." [22] Would other presuppositionalists agree?

In my view, "account for" as employed in presuppositionalist theory suggests some recognition of the hierarchical nature of knowledge, for which Objectivism is rigorously geared. [23] But this is ironic, coming from any mystical standpoint, since mysticism, insomuch as intellectual hierarchy and logical reduction are concerned, is committed to reversing the objective relationship between knowledge and emotion, which can hardly be said to be "logical." Indeed, the Bible itself makes this reversal explicit in Proverbs 1:7, which states, "The fear of the Lord is the beginning of knowledge." How should the follower of such advice account for his emotion of fear in such a case, a fear without the benefit of knowledge? We will see in the analysis that follows how this kind reversal will be very problematic for the more self-conscious and honest apologists. [24]

Furthermore, since "account for" alone does not guarantee rational validity in one's explanations, what measures are in place in the presuppositional apologetic to protect one's explanations from reaching beyond the objectively valid and "transcending" into the arbitrary? Since one can presumably continue to insist that one's explanations be "accounted for" by ever appealing to prior knowledge - particularly if one ignores the hierarchical nature of knowledge, does the presuppositional method allow for an objective stopping point to guard against infinite regress, stolen concepts, and similar errors? Obviously the answer is no if, at the end of the "accounting" which the presuppositionalist believes to offer the best solutions to his questions, we find a breach of knowledge hierarchy and the assertion of concepts genetically stripped from their objective roots (such as the idea of consciousness prior to existence), which is inevitable in any defense of mystic philosophy. Thus, it may very well be the case that the apologist's challenge that atheists "account for" certain philosophical issues, is little more than an invitation to join the apologist in his orgy of fallacy-worship. Besides, if "account means logical proof," as Mitchell has claimed, wouldn't we need to assume uniformity before we even embark on constructing proofs?

I argue that if the appeal to theism in the effort to "account for" induction commits the fallacy of the stolen concept, then its conclusions are invalid and Mr. Walker's wholesale denouncement of non-Christian philosophy is made in haste. Suffice it to say, from what we can gather so far from Mr. Walker's apologetic, induction, according to Christian presuppositionalism, is not based on the facts of reality; indeed, they are based on the "character of God." This means that the apologist's "resolution" to this so-called problem of induction rests on the primacy of consciousness view of reality, which is false because it commits the fallacy of the stolen concept (since it posits existence as a product of a conscious act). Thus the appeal to theism in an attempt to resolve conflicts associated with justifying induction, is invalid.

Moreover, if a philosophy can provide a reasonable explanation for why we are justified in assuming the orderliness of the universe without appealing to theism, then Mr. Walker's second premise is untrue and his argument is consequently refuted. And Objectivism does provide a such an explanation: Existence exists, and that which exists is that which exists independent of consciousness. These facts are implicit in all of man's perception, they must be assumed even in order to question, doubt or reject them, and they are grounded in the perceptually available facts of reality, in every entity which exists. The answer lies, literally speaking, right in front of our eyes.

The apologist will no doubt refuse to abandon his argument, and will likely attempt to preserve it by attacking the fundamentals of Objectivism in the context which I have outlined here. But how would he accomplish this? Most likely, he will argue that the Objectivist fundamentals are somehow incomplete or inadequate to fulfill the task in question, that the axiomatic concepts 'existence', 'identity' and 'consciousness' are neither primary nor irreducible, for some fantasy-indulgent reason or another. Such an attempt would amount to, according to Objectivist principles, the open advocacy of stolen concepts at the foundation of one's view of reality and knowledge. For what could be prior to the fact of existence? And this is precisely what lies at the core of all theism: the denial of the hierarchical nature of objective knowledge, the rejection of reason as one's only means of knowledge and of reality as the final court of appeal.

 

Mr. Walker's Three Follow-up Comments

After he presents his primary argument, Mr. Walker stated the following:

For the atheist to say, 'But I DO use induction.' is not a rational justification for using it. To say, 'Well the universe IS orderly.' is not a rational justification for WHY it is orderly.

Certainly I cannot object to the first sentence here. Engaging in an activity is not equivalent to a rational justification for that activity. However, and this is why I voiced my concern above about the presuppositionalist's use of "account for" in my analysis of Mr. Walker's argument, asking for a "rational justification for WHY" the universe is orderly can potentially lead to conceptually dangerous ground if the objective hierarchy of knowledge is not observed. For it is here where one must identify his affirmation of the metaphysical primacy of existence if he is to safeguard objectivity. Otherwise, he jeopardizes his view of reality to stolen concepts and frozen abstractions. Again, the reason why the universe is orderly is because existence is identity.

Mr. Walker also wrote:

The atheist COULD say (and often does), 'Well, I use induction because it works.' But what has he really said? He has simply begged the question.

This would depend on what question such a statement is offered to answer. The statement "I use induction because it works" suggests purpose fulfillment. Thus, if the question this statement is intended to answer were "Why do you use induction?" the statement "I use induction because it works" is an appropriate answer. Is it the presuppositionalist's position that induction does not work? However, Mr. Walker's point is that the use of induction is not equivalent to a rational justification of why induction works. Thus, if in answer to the question "What is a rational justification of induction?" one states "I use induction because it works," then one could make the case that such an answer is inadequate, and possibly begs the question.

And finally, Mr. Walker concluded his argument with the following statement:

We are not saying that we shouldn't trust induction or use induction. We are saying that only a Biblical worldview can provide the rational ingredients to make sense out of induction's reliability.

How can this be if in fact the biblical theist must allow for the activity of a universe-manipulating form of consciousness, a deity? How can this be when the theistic view of the world depends on the primacy of consciousness, which is invalid? If as Mr. Walker holds we posit the orderliness of the universe with the reservation that that orderliness is not absolute, but must be flexible enough to permit the volatile activity of a being capable of performing miracles (i.e., of violating the law of identity which grounds induction), then already we see that the assumed reliability of induction is completely compromised in the hands of theistic philosophy. This is basically akin to offering what the theist calls a "rational justification" for induction while denying the very principle which makes induction possible in the first place, which is the law of identity (and its application to action, which is the law of causality). Induction, therefore, in the hands of the theist, becomes a stolen concept.

If the object of our inductive thought can be A at one moment and suddenly become non-A through some kind of thaumaturgy (e.g., magic or 'miracle') which leaves no objectively traceable cause in the next moment, then induction cannot achieve any reliability to begin with (for A ceases to have reference to objective reality since its identity can be revised according to God's whimsy). If I must grant validity to the notion of miracles at any point in my view of reality (as the Christian does), such that water can be magically transformed into wine (cf. John 2:1-11), that A can become non-A through supernatural (i.e., unnatural) means of causality (e.g., by divine whim - i.e., non-causality), how can I assume the identity of any object with any certainty at all? The theist may say that the answer is faith. But how is faith a substitute for objective certainty, which I achieve through Objectivism? Indeed, wishing, hoping and fantasizing are not man's means of cognition, nor can they replace man's reliance on his own ability to reason. However, this is precisely the end result of such allegiance to folly as proposed by Christian apologists. It is a clearly unworkable sham at the very least. The Christian's alternative to Objectivism is indeed nightmarish!

I think Mr. Walker and his ilk should take their arguments back to the rhetoric mill from which they learned them, and fundamentally reconsider their positions. Religious men are by their very nature not very critical thinkers. Since their fundamental view of existence, of man and of knowledge is something which has no basis in reality and which they must accept unquestioningly, it does not come as a surprise that their arguments and treatments of competing views proceed in a superficial and procrustean manner. Bible believers, particularly those who claim that the Bible is inerrant, commonly consider it normal course to assume that the 66 books of Bible are 100% factually true and that they offer sound philosophical doctrine, even though they typically have only read a fraction of its content. This hasty allegiance to dogma is completely antithetical to critical thought, and completely incompatible with the presuppositionalists' pedantic pretenses.

As for Mr. Walker's claim about the "rational ingredients" needed to "make sense out of induction's reliability" being provided exclusively by Christian theism, I will focus my inquiry on this matter in a following section. So far, however, we have found that not only does Mr. Walker's argument not even attempt to prove the existence of a god, biblical or otherwise, it also fails to protect itself from committing the fallacy of the stolen concept, which I have found to lie at the foundation of any theistic view of reality, principally because such views (to varying extents) assert a form of consciousness as the source of existence.

 

Grounding Induction:

Mr. Walker cited the critic's statement that "[induction] predates the Judeo-Christian God as well," and then responded:

You're begging the question now. This statement would only make sense if you were assuming that the Judeo-Christian God had a beginning. Van Tillians do not grant that bald assertion. The Judeo-Christian God is the GROUND of induction. Induction cannot predate its own foundation. That's sort of like saying, "Brian predates Brian's father."

Here Mr. Walker assumes the very truth of his primary claim, namely that the Christian triune God exists, and that this triune God is "the GROUND of induction," which are the very claims in dispute. Thus, he is guilty of the very charge he accuses his critic to have committed. This gains for his overall argument no mileage whatsoever.

Furthermore, he assumes that his god-belief is not a human invention. But there are good reasons to suspect that god-belief is a human invention. For one thing, all claims for God's existence are learned from other men. For example, there is no constellation of stars which clearly and unmistakably spell out God's name or unequivocally testifies of God's existence. We do not look at the face of the moon and find inscribed among its geographical formations the words "Jesus saves," like a flashing neon sign on a church which gains its primary revenue on bingo night.

So-called "sacred writings" or "scriptures" claimed to be divinely inspired were penned, reproduced, edited and compiled by men, and are claimed by men to be the word of God. Scholars have been able to approximate the date of these writings, and although there might not be unanimity on their results, this has made it possible for us to determine when in history certain ideas were introduced to various communities and to human culture in general. And since even the earliest human beings would have had to have engaged in inductive reasoning in order to survive, even if only on a primitive level by comparison to human thinking today, there is certainly good reason to accept the view that induction precedes the development of Judeo-Christian theism, as Mr. Walker's critic stated.

Furthermore, when we review the history of god-belief, we discover that it evolves just like any other human field of thought, just like philosophy, technology or art. In fact, religion is a primitive form of philosophy, since it is an attempt to address man's primary needs and to give him a comprehensive view of reality and his life. This alone does not make religious claims true or even valid, nor does it prove that religion is suitable for man's life. The religionist has either to ignore these facts, or to downplay them, in order to assert the eternal validity of his god-beliefs, in the manner in which Mr. Walker does here. And if in his arguments for the existence of God the apologist assumes this eternal validity in spite of all these reasons confirming the proposal that god-belief is a human invention, he again begs the question.

In addition to these points, we would be wise to draw our attention to the fact that there are literally hundreds of variations on religious belief, which we would expect if god-belief were a human invention. Within Christianity alone [25], there are literally hundreds of different denominations, sects, subsects and subcults, many of which have split off from other denominations or sects due to disputed interpretations of scripture, a good many of which claim exclusive possession of the proper Christian truths. Many apologists rationalize this embarrassing fact by interpreting such division in its own dogmatic terms (e.g., that such division is the result of man's "sin nature"), or by denying that such splintering has any detrimental significance at all. [26]

 

The "Rational Ingredients" of Induction:

Above, we saw in Mr. Walker's primary argument for Christian theism the claim that "only a Biblical worldview can provide the rational ingredients to make sense out of induction's reliability." What are those "rational ingredients" to which Mr. Walker alludes, where do they come from, how would we be aware of them, and, specifically, how do they integrate to form a rational justification of induction? These are some of the questions which I will now explore, and in so doing I refer to another portion of Mr. Walker's overall apologetic.

Mr. Walker's non-believing critic wrote:

This is no different (or substantial) an argument than if I were to say that "Fred, the toad in my garden is the creator of all things. I and others have built up an impressive worldview around Fred that makes immanent sense to us."

Mr. Walker responds:

"It's VERY different. Fred would have to be eternal, self-existent, immutable, orderly and all the other attributes of the Biblical God in order to provide a rational justification for induction. In other words, Fred would have to be God, and God is not a toad."

This is where the rubber meets the road for Mr. Walker's argument and where its devastating refutation finds its most practical impetus. Here Mr. Walker has stated what he believes to be the essential "ingredients," so to speak, of the rational justification of induction that he's looking for, which he expects others to find in the assertion of the "Christian God."

Essentially, what Mr. Walker holds to be the foundation of induction, the uniformity of nature, the laws of logic, human dignity, and objective morality, must be something that is:

[1] "eternal"

[2] "self-existent"

[3] "immutable"

[4] "orderly"

[5] and "all the other attributes of the Biblical God"

In the case of the first four attributes which Mr. Walker names, I see no reason to think the ascription of these qualities to a god or any other "supernatural being" is justified, especially when Objectivism holds that these apply to its own starting point, which is the fact that existence exists. I must resist passing judgment, however, in the case of the fifth ascription - "all the other attributes of the Biblical God" - since many of the qualities which Christians ascribe to the biblical god are anti-conceptual to begin with, and those that are not may very well have nothing to do with a "rational justification for induction. I will briefly step through these qualities one by one to determine their relevance to the matter in question.

[1] Eternal: Mr. Walker wants to point to something that is 'eternal' as singularly supplying a "rational justification for induction."

The facts of the case are, that:

Existence is eternal.

Eternal is defined as 'without beginning or end, everlasting' (Webster's II New Riverside Dictionary, sv 'eternal'), 'having infinite duration' or 'continued without intermission' (Merriam-Webster's Collegiate Dictionary (online) sv. 'eternal': http://www.m-w.com/cgi-bin/dictionary).

Dr. Peikoff argues thus:

Time is the measurement of motion: as such, it is a type of relationship. Time applies only within [emphasis Thorn] the universe, when you define a standard - such as the motion of the earth around the sun. If you take that as a unit, you can say: 'This person has a certain relationship to that motion; he has existed for three revolutions; he is three years old.' But when you get to the universe as a whole, obviously no standard is applicable. You cannot get outside the universe. The universe is eternal in the literal sense: non-temporal, out of time. [27]

Since time can only apply within existence (as a relationship between distinct objects), the attempt to apply time as a measure to the totality of existence is incoherent (since all objects are included within that totality, thus leaving nothing with which the totality can have a relationship). The only valid option open to man is to recognize that existence is eternal.

Thus, the fact that existence exists fulfills this pre-conditional requirement to induction which Mr. Walker cites. And what's more, is the fact that existence is perceptually self-evident, i.e., axiomatic. There is no need to resort to faith claims or to assert the supernatural to recognize the fact that existence exists. One merely need open his eyes and be aware of his environment directly.

 

[2] Self-existent: Mr. Walker wants to point to something that is also 'self-existent' as singularly supplying a "rational justification for induction."

The facts of the matter are:

Existence is self-existent.

Existence is neither created nor destructible. One cannot argue that existence depends upon 'something prior' to existence in order to "account for" existence. Such an argument would have no explanatory value, since it would still have to posit the existence of something as being responsible for existence. Otherwise it would constitute an appeal to non-existence, and of course that is the substance of religion anyway. In other words, one must assume the fact of existence in order to attempt either to prove existence, or to dispute it. Either option commits those who choose it to the fallacy of the stolen concept.

 

[3] Immutable: Mr. Walker wants to point to something that is also 'immutable' as singularly supplying a "rational justification for induction."

The facts of the matter are:

Existence is immutable. I.e., the fact that existence exists does not change.

What could change the fact that existence exists? Non-existence? If one were to claim that "it is possible that existence could go out of existence," where would it go?

Even to argue for such positions (for whatever purpose), one would first have to presuppose existence just by crafting an argument, and would presuppose existence in the very solution to such imaginary imbroglios. In other words, a position that would attempt to hold that the fact that existence exists is not immutable would negate itself in any assumption of permanence or immutability (permanence or immutability of what?).

In fact, when Mr. Walker's critic conceded that "Little is permanent in the atheist worldview" [28], Mr. Walker responded with: "Which is why they [meaning atheists] have no rational justification for the use of induction." But if all that is needed for a rational justification of induction is something in nature which is immutable, permanent or not subject to change, we have it: the fact that existence exists does not change. For the theist to accept this, even implicitly (indeed, he must), he concedes the tight and streamlined rationality of Objectivism. And for the theist to insist that something "prior to" existence is required to "account for" the fact that existence exists does not change, is to endorse stolen concepts flagrantly and invalidate the foundation of his entire worldview. There is nothing "prior to existence."

 

[4] Orderly: Mr. Walker wants to point to something that is also 'orderly' as singularly supplying a "rational justification for induction."

The facts of the matter are:

Existence exists, and to exist is to be something.

The Law of Identity, which is a corollary to the fact that existence exists, is the recognition that, for A to exist, it must be A. I.e., existence is identity. This fundamental, irreversible and inviolate fact is the essential pre-condition to induction. The Law of Identity is literally universal: It applies wherever existence exist. And the totality of existence is subsumed by the concept 'universe', which includes all things which exist or are postulated to exist. For something to be included in the class of existents, it must a) be part of the universe, and b) be itself (i.e., not A and non-A). Something need only exist for a) and b) to apply.

It is because of the fact that existence is identity that man is capable of induction. As explained above, any attempt to explain the fact of existence by appealing to something "prior to" existence commits the fallacy of the stolen concept. Thus, the anticipated objection pleading for the Objectivist to "account for" the fact of existence is the insistence that the Objectivist join the mystic in his indulgence of stolen concepts. [29]

[5] "All the other attributes of the Biblical God": Mr. Walker wants to point to something, in addition to possessing all the prior qualities he mentioned specifically, which also possesses "all the other attributes of the Biblical God," as singularly supplying a "rational justification for induction."

The facts of the matter are:

The qualities attributed to God by the (authors of the) Bible are plenty and numerous. It is not surprising that Mr. Walker does not identify any of these other qualities, not because there are so many, but because in naming them he would quickly expose the nonsensical nature of his position on the matter of induction. To explore Mr. Walker's position in more depth, and to establish my verdict that it is nonsensical, I have gathered below a number of those attributes from the second chapter of the Westminster Confession of Faith, as well as a few which I have found by reading other sources, including the Bible itself, and have examined the question of whether or not those attributes are pre-conditional to induction.

They are:

[a] God is incomprehensible: The Westminster Confession of Faith cites I Kings 8:27 as substantiation of the claim that God is incomprehensible. Thus incomprehensibility must be an attribute of the biblical God. The Merriam-Webster Collegiate Dictionary defines 'incomprehensible' as 'impossible to comprehend' and 'unintelligible'. How can something which is supposed to be incomprehensible qualify as a pre-condition to induction? Mr. Walker does not say. But clearly, induction as a means of gaining understanding about the world would not be possible if it were true that its foundations were unintelligibility and if the impossibility to comprehend reality were an absolute. Were the foundations of induction unintelligibility and the impossibility to comprehend reality, then induction would not only be impossible, it would not achieve anything for man. Perhaps Mr. Walker neglected to specify this attribute of God for a good reason.

[b] God is perfect: The Westminster Confession of Faith cites Matthew 5:48 as substantiation for the claim that God is perfect. And since Mr. Walker claims that "all the other attributes of the Biblical God" are the accountable preconditions of induction, he must consequently hold that perfection - as one of these "attributes of the Biblical God" - is a precondition of induction. Since it is unlikely that any Christian would admit that the God of his worship is in any sense imperfect, we must assume that, when the Christian claims that God is perfect, he means that God is perfect in every conceivable sense. While this leads to certain problems when attempting to integrate this claim with other claims (such as the claim that "God has a purpose"), what is important in the present matter of concern is whether or not perfection is in any way a prerequisite to induction. How perfection is a pre-condition to induction is not explained by Mr. Walker, however it follows from his claim that "all the other attributes of the Biblical God" must be assumed in order to "justify" induction, that he holds that the attribute perfection or the presumption thereof is somehow pre-conditional to induction.

[c] God is infinite: The Westminster Confession of Faith cites both Exodus 3:14 and Job 11:7-9 as substantiating the claim that God is infinite. But the concept 'infinite' can only apply to potentiality, not to actuality, for it "denotes merely a potentiality of indefinite addition or subdivision." [30] Claiming that an entity is infinite in nature is essentially claiming that that entity has no particular identity, but that it has potentially any identity except a specific identity. Thus an "actually infinite being" must be a non-existent being. Mr. Walker never explains how induction depends on the pre-condition of the infinite (or non-existent), and indeed this silence does not come as a surprise. For induction indeed depends on the pre-conditions that existence exists, and that existence is identity (i.e., finite).

[d] God is invisible: The Westminster Confession of Faith cites I Timothy 1:17 as supporting the claim that God is "invisible." This means that God cannot be observed by man's sense of sight. In fact, Christians typically hold that God is not perceivable to man by any of his five senses, be it by sight, hearing, touch, scent or taste (their own descriptions of religious experience only suggest that God is "perceivable" by their emotions, even though emotions are not a form of perception). Nor will Christians typically agree that man can perceive God by any instrumental means, such as through an electron microscope or an radio wave transmitter. However, it is difficult to see how those like Mr. Walker who affirm that "all the other attributes of the Biblical God" are necessary to "provide a rational justification of induction," can maintain such a view, particularly if invisibility is listed among those attributes in question. For as we saw in the definition of induction provided above, observation is of primary concern to induction. But how can induction proceed if invisibility is an attribute which must belong to the pre-conditional foundations of induction, and observation is integral to the means of induction? Mr. Walker does not say, nor is it likely that Mr. Walker has thought his remarks through in this respect. Since we cannot observe what is forever invisible to us, invisibility per se cannot be considered to be a fundamental to inductive reasoning. Consequently we can only wonder how believers like Mr. Walker distinguish between "the invisible" and the non-existent.

[e] God is omnibenevolent or all-good: The Westminster Confession of Faith cites Exodus 34:6 as supporting the claim that God is "abundant in goodness." While this verse does not claim that God is "all-good" or omnibenevolent, it is unlikely that many Christians would admit that God is not omnibenevolent or 'all-good', for such a concession would only imply the idea that God's perfection is open to compromise.

Regardless of this, however, since the concept 'goodness' requires reference to a standard which is universal within the context of its application (such as the health of man's body when one asserts that "nourishment is good for man's health"), we must recognize that the very determination of goodness is itself the result of induction. Therefore, it is difficult to see how one would defend the claim that 'omnibenevolence' is somehow pre-conditional to induction. To argue such is to endorse the fallacy of the stolen concept, since 'goodness' is ejected from its cognitive, hierarchical roots in order to be asserted as an element of "justification" of induction. Indeed, we need induction in order to determine whether or not something is good.

[f] God is omniscient: The Westminster Confession of Faith cites Hebrews 4:13 and Psalms 147:5 in substantiation of the claim that God is "all knowing," i.e., omniscient. Omniscience, according to one source [31], is "the divine attribute of perfect knowledge," and "is exclusively His attribute" - i.e., God's attribute and only God's. Thus, omniscience, or "perfect knowledge," as an alleged attribute of God, must be, for individuals who claim as Mr. Walker does, a precondition to induction. However, it is difficult to see how this claim can bear scrutiny, primarily for the fact that, if anything, induction does not presume exhaustive knowledge of anything, but explicitly the reverse.

The notion of "perfect knowledge," or knowledge which is exhaustive of all that is actual, possible and/or imaginable, does not itself presuppose that knowledge is a product of any kind of method, such as induction. For a method of deriving new knowledge explicitly presupposes that certain knowledge is not known. Thus, since 'omniscience' in essential terms actually means possession of knowledge without means, the idea of omniscience, and both the concept of and preconditions to induction, are obviously incompatible with each other. Induction is a means of acquiring new knowledge, not a claim to possess knowledge already. This is indisputable. But a being which is said to possess all knowledge (i.e., 'omniscience' or 'perfect, infallible knowledge') has no use for induction, for induction would only lead to knowledge that is already known by the omniscient. In this respect, Mr. Walker's claim is incoherent and unsalvageable. [32]

[g] God is infallible: The Westminster Confession of faith cites Romans 11:33-34 and Psalms 147:5 in support of the claim that God is infallible. Thus, infallibility must be one of the biblical God's attributes, and therefore, according to Mr. Walker's statement, a precondition required for induction. But exactly how is infallibility a precondition essential to a "rational justification of induction"? Just as we saw in the case of God's alleged omniscience above, infallibility would negate any need for induction, since those who are infallible (or who claim to be infallible) would have no use for such a means of acquiring knowledge. Furthermore, induction alone does not guarantee man that the knowledge he achieves through inductive means will be correct, since he is neither infallible nor omniscient. Clearly infallibility cannot be a precondition to induction or a component justifying one's reliance on induction. So again we have another strike against Mr. Walker's position.

[h]God is merciful: The Westminster Confession of Faith cites Exodus 34:6-7 in support of the claim that God is merciful. While Christians may in fact believe this to be true about their deity, it is difficult to see how such an attribute is, as Mr. Walker's statements above suggest, essential to induction or to a "rational justification of induction." Mercy, according to rational philosophy, is "unearned forgiveness." [33] How is mercy or unearned forgiveness essential to induction? Mr. Walker does not say. Indeed, it is difficult to see how any matter of forgiveness, whether earned or, in the case of Christian pursuits, unearned, has anything to do with a "rational justification of induction."

[i] God is omnipotent: The New Unger's Bible Dictionary (s.v. 'omnipotence') cites Gen. 17:1; Ex. 15:11-12; Deut. 3:24; Pss. 62.:11; 65:6; 147:5; Jer. 32:17; Matt. 6:13; 19:26; Eph. 3:20; and Rev. 19:6 in substantiation of the claim that God is "omnipotent." Thus, omnipotence as such must be one of God's attributes, and as such, according to Mr. Walker's claim, essential to a rational justification of induction. But how can this be? I know of no reason why one should accept the notion 'omnipotence' as a legitimate concept; it is an expression of fantasy and wishful thinking. So already I consider this assumption, necessitated by Mr. Walker's broad claim, to be quite dubious.

Furthermore, even if one does grant conceptual legitimacy to the notion 'omnipotence', it is still up to those who believe as Mr. Walker does to demonstrate how induction presupposes - or somehow requires the presence, activity or precondition of - omnipotence in order to be rationally justified. What do either of the two have essentially to do with each other? Indeed, it is not even apparent how induction based on the observable could arrive at the notion 'omnipotence', let alone how omnipotence figures into the rational development of induction. Clearly Mr. Walker has some homework to do here!

[j] God is awesome or awe-inspiring: Turning from the more dogmatic statement of faith assembled by the Westminster Confession to the hard turf of biblical lore, we find many attributes of the biblical God which are not quite so user-friendly. For instance, many Christians hold that God is awesome or awe-inspiring. Scriptural references to support this view may include Psalms 4:4, 33:8 and 119:161. The Merriam-Webster Collegiate Dictionary (online) defines 'awe' as "an emotion variously combining dread, veneration, and wonder that is inspired by authority or by the sacred or sublime"; 'awesome' as "expressive of awe." But how one particular emotion as opposed to another, or how its expression, is pre-conditional to induction, is not explained. Indeed, any emotions that over-power an individual may indeed interfere with one's inductive pursuits, particularly if one does not comprehend the essential distinction between knowledge and emotion.

[k] God is jealous: The Bible states that God is jealous (cf. Exodus 20:5 et al.). [34] If as Mr. Walker suggests, all the attributes of the Biblical God must be present in order to formulate a rational justification of induction, then he must think that jealousy, clearly being attributed to the Biblical God according to its primary source, is a necessary component to that rational justification of induction of which he speaks. But how so? How can jealousy - an emotion as such, petty as it is - be integral to the foundations of induction? Like envy, jealousy is hostility toward a perceived rival or one believed to enjoy a desired advantage, and thus an emotional response to one's unfulfilled desire for the unearned. As such, it is far from a positive emotion.

But the Bible clearly makes the mistake of claiming that emotion holds epistemological primacy over knowledge (cf. Proverbs 1:7, et al.), and therefore, for believers to figure that emotions hold primacy over reason and the means of rational identification of the objective reality, is not very surprising. However, all of this points to an unmistakable commitment to epistemological subjectivism, where one's confusion of emotion with knowledge results in the compromise of the latter, and the psychological unhealthiness of the former. Surely, jealousy as such is no essential to induction! On this point, Mr. Walker's claim clearly fails.

[l] God is wrathful: In many instances the Bible characterizes God as being monstrously wrathful. [35] Thus, if Mr. Walker holds that all "attributes of the Biblical God" are required "in order to provide a rational justification for induction," and if one of the attributes of God is wrathfulness, then Mr. Walker must assume that wrathfulness as such is a precondition to induction. But this is highly suspicious, even absurd.

The essential question in this survey is in determining whether or not the attributes of God - including the attribute of wrathfulness - is pre-conditional to induction, as implied by Mr. Walker's claim that "all the other attributes of the Biblical God" are needed in order to "justify" induction. If Mr. Walker's claim is true, then how does wrathfulness at all figure in the "rational justification of induction"? Mr. Walker does not say, and it may very well be the case that Mr. Walker spoke in haste and did not anticipate such questions. However, Mr. Walker has a lot of explaining to do if he wants to reverse my verdict that his primary apologetic position is untenable.

[m] God is loving: The Westminster Confession of Faith cites I John 4:8 and 4:16 in support for the claim that God is loving (in fact, both passages state that "God is love"). Love is man's emotional response to his values. But values are chosen by man after some recognition of the facts of reality has already been achieved, which requires inductive reasoning and value judgments. Thus, it is difficult to see how the attribute of loving can apply as a precondition to induction. This attribute, insomuch as the theist may want to claim that it is essential to a rational justification of induction, suffers from the same problems as the Biblical God's attribute jealousy, as seen above. Furthermore, there are excellent reasons why the deity portrayed in the Bible could not love. [36]

[n] God is scheming: God is said by Christians to have a plan, an absolute, far-reaching, apocalyptic plan of such immense proportions that it is literally beyond man's ability to comprehend (another point of incomprehensibility in the attributes of "the Biblical God"). Thus, God is seen as constantly scheming in the devices of fulfilling his plan. [37] How can the attribute of scheming at all serve as one of the "rational ingredients of induction"? But if it were the case that all attributes of the Christian God are needed in order to provide a rational justification of induction, we would clearly need to include the attribute of scheming into that account. However, to entertain such an undertaking is preposterous.

[o] God is deceitful: I Kings 22:23, II Chronicles 18:22, Jeremiah 20:7 and 4:10, and Ezekiel 14:9 all show that the biblical God deceives men intentionally. Thus, the Christian God comes with the attribute of deceitfulness included in its sacred packaging. But what do deceit and deceitfulness have to do with induction? There is nothing which Mr. Walker states in his message shows how this can be answered in order to keep his overall apologetic intact. Indeed, if deceit and deceitfulness are rudimentary to induction according to Christianity, as suggested here, this should tell us a lot.

[p] God is immortal: While many may argue that immortality is encompassed by the attribute that God is eternal (see above), the two concepts are not equivalent or interchangeable. 'Immortality' means "exempt from death" and is attributed to (mythical) animate beings which are said to be living and which would otherwise die if not immortal. Now man is obviously not "exempt from death," but man is capable of induction. So how is immortality a precondition of induction?

I Timothy 1:17 states that God is immortal, and therefore immortality as such belongs to the list of the biblical God's alleged attributes and thus must be considered in this analysis. We saw above that the idea of eternality is covered by the very fact of existence: since existence exists, and since time can only apply within the context of existence, existence as such is literally eternal, i.e., out of time. However, is existence immortal? This notion would only apply in the case that existence as such were a life form, but this is not the case. The concept 'Life' only applies to a certain class of existents, living organisms, and thus is not universally applicable to all entities. Many entities do not belong to the class living organisms and therefore concepts which presuppose life cannot apply (e.g., we do not refer to a pebble or a grain of sand as immortal in any sense of the term).

But how does the attribute immortality relate to induction, or more specifically, to the foundations of induction and to a "rational justification of induction"? Sadly, Mr. Walker is silent on this matter. But since immortality is an attribute of the Biblical God, this attribute would have to be essential to a rational justification of induction, if Mr. Walker's assertion had merit. Indeed, Mr. Walker's claim is untenable, for induction is used by men, and men are not immortal; indeed, they are mortal, and this fact, far from the notion of immortality, is a primary reason why man requires induction in the first place (since he needs to acquire and validate knowledge of reality in order to survive). Thus, in the package-deal Mr. Walker would have us accept, man would have to deny a primary fact of his very being - that of being mortal and facing the alternative of life or death - in order to "provide a rational justification of induction." This would be absurd.

[q] God is threatening: The threatening nature of the God of the Bible is clearly self-evident from any first reading. The God of the Bible is portrayed as possessing virtually unlimited power. [38] The God of the Bible is also portrayed as given to passionate mood swings of anger, wrath and "divine justice" which amounts to the condemnation of man for the very nature this God Himself gave to man. [39] That one must believe in order to "enter the Kingdom of God" and in order to escape the "lake of fire," is a manifestation of the threatening nature of the God in which Christian put their faith. As Hebrews 10:31 says "It is a fearful thing to fall into the hands of the living God."

Clearly threats and threatening action is actually antagonistic to all reasoning, including induction. One does not reason by force or by the threat of force. On the contrary, one reasons by choice, which means that the proper conditions for reasoning is freedom, not threats. Obedience to commands out of deference to fearing someone's threats of force or psychological coercion is the choice to act in spite of his own reasoning. This means that one's actions should be irrelevant to his own verdicts, whether they are properly or improperly formed.

Does induction presuppose the threatening nature of the Christian God? If so, what do threats have to do with inductive reasoning? Of course, Mr. Walker does not say. He merely exclaims that all the attributes of the Christian God are necessary to provide for a rational justification of induction. Such a generalization, on this point alone, should we grant that the character of the Christian God poses any kind of threat to man (and according to the Bible, it does!), is prima facie arbitrary and untenable. And to boot, such threats are supposed to be against those who employ their reason and come to conclusions not approved by the priests (and thus constitute an affront against both man and reason as such), but these threats ironically only work against those who believe them and their mystical premises. So far from being a precondition for induction as Mr. Walker might have us believe, the threatening nature of the biblical God only represents the mystic's hostility to reason.

Given the above analysis, I conclude that all of these characteristics, [a] through [q], as well as a litany of others, are clearly non-essential to a "justification of induction." Certainly, Mr. Walker has some explaining to do before his position, as indicated by his own words above, can be considered to have any merit whatsoever. But, as attributes of an unchanging God, they are, according to Mr. Walker's assertion above, necessary for a rational justification of induction per Christianity. I could have enlarged my analysis to include a review of yet additional qualities ascribed to the Christian God (e.g., righteous, holy, opposed to sin, supernatural, non-corporeal, three-headed or "trinitarian," et al.), but I suspect my readers already get the point from what analysis I have provided. It is clear that, given what has been exposed so far, Mr. Walker's attempt to "ground" induction in the deity of Judeo-Christian mysticism, is wholly misguided.

More importantly, Mr. Walker's statements about the foundations and philosophical justification of induction show no concern for the primary facts of reality (i.e., the axioms, the laws of identity and causality, etc.), the nature of man's consciousness, the role of perception in man's awareness of reality, or the importance of objective concept-formation. How can one expect to "justify" induction without consideration of these important points? Perhaps Mr. Walker takes these things for granted, or perhaps he feels they are not relevant to the issue. What Mr. Walker's argument strongly suggests is that the relevant facts of the matter are secondary to an appeal to authority which determines how those facts are supposed to be interpreted in terms of his confessional investment (i.e., by "divine decree" or, essentially, by whim). But on what basis would an appeal to authority find any philosophical merit if one cannot first determine the facts necessary to settle such questions as "which authority is properly authoritative?" - a question for which we would need induction! Certainly, this cannot be considered rational.

Consequently, given the above analysis, here are the reasons in brief why Mr. Walker's overall apologetic in regard to a "rational justification of induction" fails:

  1. The first four conditions which Mr. Walker specifies as essential to man's induction are fulfilled by the fact of existence through Objectivism and not by appealing to a universe-creating consciousness beyond man's perception, as argued by "presuppositionalist" apologetics.
  2. The recognition and consistent use of those conditions are actually undermined by the notion 'god' and Christian theism in general (because of their commitment to the primacy of consciousness view of reality and its general view of man as an essentially impotent being [40]).
  3. Mr. Walker's idea that "all the other attributes of the Biblical God" are essential to induction is irreparably untenable.
  4. The question of the means of one's awareness of the agent which the presuppositionalist claims to be responsible for the conditions held to be necessary for induction (e.g., how does one know that a god exists and that this being provides the rational grounds of induction?) is not clarified by presuppositionalism's argumentative strategies.

If Mr. Walker wishes to maintain that Christian theism as such is necessary to "account for" the preconditions of induction, I must conclude that his position is itself the result of poor induction.

 

The Theist's Real Agenda:

What does Mr. Walker really want to posit as the singular "rational justification of induction"? Clearly, what Mr. Walker wants to posit as a precondition of induction is not consciousness as such, but the metaphysical primacy of consciousness.

In every case, whether the element to which Mr. Walker pointed may be found to be legitimately connected to a "rational justification of induction" or not, what lurks behind the chimera of his ostensive concern for rational standards is the assertion of a universe-creating, reality-ruling consciousness, a 'mega-consciousness' which allegedly possesses each of these traits inherently, by its nature ('God'). As such, the gargantuan package-deal represented by this deity takes the starring role as the single precondition necessary to any rational justification of induction. This explicitly entails the primacy of consciousness view of reality, that a form of consciousness rather than the facts of reality dictates the nature of man's norms of reasoning and means of acquiring knowledge - essentially that things are the way they are because someone wants them to be that way. So we find that the apologist is merely hijacking legitimate epistemological issues, such as the justification of induction, in order to smuggle his primacy of consciousness premises into the realm of rational debate.

But what justifies the primacy of consciousness? This is the question that the apologist will never be able to answer without resorting to the stolen concepts that make the position of the primacy of consciousness seem viable to men. However, since apologists for religious claims avoid phrasing their arguments in terms of essentialized fundamentals (e.g., the issue of metaphysical primacy), but instead prefer vague, mystically embroidered terms which can be defined by the expedience of the moment (e.g., 'God', 'creator', etc.) even they do not recognize the need to validate their most basic premise, which is the assumption that consciousness holds metaphysical primacy over existence.

The answer to all theistic enterprise and apologetics, rather than bothering with tiresome discussions about issues like induction, is simply to identify one's starting points: to recognize that existence exists, that to exist is to be something (the law of identity) that man can identify that existence exists by the direct appeal of his senses (the fact of consciousness). This leaves basically only one option for the apologist who holds that there is no common ground between believers and non-believers on which to base his initial starting points, and that is: insist that the non-believer "account for" the fact that existence exists. This is nothing short of an invitation to join the theist in accepting his stolen concepts. The attentive non-believer, however, will recognize this invitation to error, and simply leave the mystic begging his own questions and pining for company to his misery, unindulged.

The theist's problem essentially lies in his rejection of the law of identity. Of course, theists in general will usually not come out and say openly that they reject the law of identity. Instead, a less direct approach is preferred, such as Mr. Walker's parenthetical qualification which we saw above to the effect that the uniformity of nature is not absolute. In spite of such reservations, theists will typically claim that their doctrines not only adhere to the law of identity, but that one cannot assume the validity and applicability of the law of identity without granting, either explicitly or implicitly, the presupposed validity of their god-beliefs. A little dose of philosophical detection is sufficient to expose this.

For instance, the theist wants to posit a supernatural entity as the sustainer of identity, thus ensuring the viability of induction by ensuring the stability of the metaphysical (i.e., of reality). This course of reasoning operates on the assumption that an entity's existence is insufficient to guarantee (or "account for") its own identity as an absolute. It is not enough that a rock exists in order for the rock in question to have a finite nature (i.e., to be a rock), goes the theist's assumption. A form of consciousness (i.e., "God") is required to guarantee (i.e., "account for") this, claims the apologist.

Thus, implicit in the presuppositional huss of the apologist's argument is the inferred principle that an entity's identity requires something outside itself to provide the entity with its identity - as if to give the entity "metaphysical currency." Without that something outside itself to guarantee (or "account for") its identity, it would presumably have a random identity, i.e., any identity but its own specific identity, i.e., no specific identity. The apologist presumably takes such ideas seriously and insists that they have philosophical significance.

But when the apologist gets to God, he argues that this principle - which as previously asserted as an inviolable absolute when applied to the context of the universe as a whole ('universe' here assumed by the apologist to be a product of God's "creative" act) - no longer applies. God, they say, does not require any outside agent in order to have His own identity; His identity is necessitated by virtue of His existence. In other words, God is posited as an exception to a principle of the apologist's own making, a principle earlier treated as if it were absolute and inviolable, for God, he claims, does not require anything beyond himself in order to guarantee (or "account for") his (God's) identity. But if the theist accepts that it is possible that one entity can have its own identity by virtue of its existence (i.e., apart from the providence of something outside it), why can it not be that way for the whole universe of things? As one non-believer reasoned, "If we need to postulate a God to have created this universe, then who or what created God? And if He didn't require a creator, then why did our universe?" [41]

 

Can we expect honesty from the apologist?

Curiously, on 04 May 2000 [42], Mr. Walker offered a response to the following question from a critic of the presuppositionalist attitude:

The critic asked, "I am curious, would knocking out one of these 5 pillars of yours from under your particular TAG Christian worldview invalidate it in your eyes?" And Mr. Walker responded:

Well, in order to "knock out one of these 5 pillars" you would have to change the attributes of God. Since God is immutable (unchanging), that would not be possible.

Notice that Mr. Walker offers no straight answer here. He never admits that the identification of a genuine flaw in his apologetic will be sufficient to demonstrate its invalidity. Instead, he blatantly evades the question by repeating his claim that refutation is impossible. His defense amounts essentially to the reiteration of the claim that "God is immutable (unchanging)," which simply begs the very question at issue here. How's that for honesty?

In compliance with this, since he confirms the belief common to various forms of Christianity that, since God is "immutable" the attributes of God therefore cannot change, Mr. Walker must believe that God's jealous and wrathful nature never changes. Who's to say that God's jealousy will not be invoked when believers make it to heaven and embark to enjoy its alleged paradise, or that God's wrath will not be kindled by His own jealousy? After all, if earth and its populace of sinners is gone, and hell has already swallowed those destined for it, can one say that God's wrath will have been appeased, particularly if God and all his attributes are unchanging? [43]

 

Conclusion:

Far from making a plausible case for any of the conclusions Mr. Walker has asserted in regard to his god-belief, he offers us a series of untenable claims and poorly constructed inferences which casts serious doubt on the efficacy of presuppositionalist apologetics in relation to induction. Given the analysis I present above, I see no conclusion possible other than to dismiss Mr. Walker's reasoning as trite and vacuous. Apologists seeking to establish the alleged legitimacy of their god-belief commitments should consult other models, for Mr. Walker's suffers from serious faults.

_____________________________

Notes

 

[1] While presuppositionalism broadly refers to an argument scheme, presuppositionalists themselves seem to think that they are in possession of a single argument type which accomplishes their ends. However, the exact nature of this argument type, known as the "transcendental argument for the existence of God," is subject to considerable debate among presuppositionalists themselves. S. Joel Garver, in his A Primer on Presuppositionalism, states, "There's no such thing as the transcendental argument. What there are, are transcendental strategies for defending the Faith against unbelief."

[2] See Martin's essay Does Induction Presume the Existence of the Christian God? found on the Secular Web.

[3] Mr. Choi's statement can be found in this message to the Apologia e-Group Discussion list (archives for this list are publicly accessible). It should be mentioned that Mr. Choi's characterization of atheism suggests that atheism draws specifically from Humean philosophy in regard to the issue of induction. Not only can this connection be shown to be unnecessary, contrary to what many presuppositionalist apologists assume to be the case, Choi's position appears to be a case of purposely stacking the deck against those who believe contrary to the presuppositionalist's religious claims. Development of a comprehensive Objectivist response to such suggestion of course lies outside the scope of this present essay. Until I have had the time and opportunity to draft such a response myself, I recommend those who are interested in this particular matter to get a copy of Dr. David Kelley's lectures "The Primacy of Existence" (1985) and "Universals and Induction" (1988), which offer a well-needed exposé of the errors of the Humean metaphysics and approach to induction. Both lectures are available through Principle Source.

[4] "Philosophy: Who Needs It," Philosophy: Who Needs It, (New York: Signet, 1984), p. 2.

[5] "The Chickens' Homecoming," The New Left: The Anti-Industrial Revolution, (New York: Signet, 1971), p. 107.

[6] However, Objectivism readily identifies how skepticism and mysticism are two faces of the same coin. As Leonard Peikoff notes,

If mysticism advocates the promiscuous acceptance of ideas, skepticism advocates their promiscuous doubt. The mystic "just knows" whatever he wants to believe; the skeptic "just doesn't know" whatever he wants not to believe. The operative term and guiding force here is "wants," i.e., feeling. Both viewpoints reduce to emotionalism; both represent the reliance on feeling as a cognitive guide. Both represent a denial of man's need of logic and an enshrinement of the arbitrary. ("Mysticism and Skepticism as Denials of Reason," Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand, p. 183.)

For Objectivist responses to certainty-rejecting skepticism, see Rand, "Galt's Speech," For the New Intellectual, (New York: Signet, 1961), pp. 154-155; "Consciousness and Identity," Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology, Expanded Second Edition. Harry Binswanger and Leonard Peikoff, ed., (New York: Meridian, 1990) p. 79; Leonard Peikoff, "Maybe You're Wrong," The Objectivist Forum, (April, 1981), pp. 8-12; et al. For Objectivist responses to reality-rejecting rationalism, see Rand, "For the New Intellectual," For the New Intellectual, p. 30; Andrew Bernstein, "The Primacy of Consciousness Versus the Objectivist Metaphysics," (audio: Second Renaissance Books, 1993), tape 2, side A; et al. See also my Objectivist links page for more general information about the Philosophy of Reason.

[7] It was a commandment which Jesus gave to his audiences that they believe. Indeed, Jesus commanded the ruler of the synagogue, "Be not afraid, only believe" (Mark 5:36).

Jesus promised condemnation to hellfire to those who do not believe. Mark 16:16 has Jesus say, "He that believeth and is baptized shall be saved; but he that believeth not shall be damned."

Similarly, John 3:18 has Jesus say, "He that believeth on him is not condemned: but he that believeth not is condemned already, because he hath not believed in the name of the only begotten Son of God." And the 36th verse of that same chapter reiterates this position: "He that believeth on the Son hath everlasting life: and he that believeth not the Son shall not see life; but the wrath of God abideth on him."

Clearly, the Bible threatens those who do not believe its claims with condemnation, torment and suffering.

The author of the Epistle to the Hebrews considered unbelief to be linked to an "evil heart" (3:12), and that unbelief is sufficient to keep men from enjoying salvation (3:18-19).

The Bible, particularly the New Testament, posits the notion of 'hell' as a constant reminder to believers that the punishment for non-belief (or heretical belief) and disobedience is eternal torment in the inextinguishable flames of the "lake of fire" (Rev. 20:10-14).

And in Revelation 21:8 we learn that the "unbelieving… shall have their part in the lake which burneth with fire and brimstone…" Clearly, unbelief as such is condemnable, according to the Bible, and the consequence for unbelief is eternal torture and suffering.

Many more such verses can be found which support the indictment that the Bible threatens men who do not believe, yet these should suffice.

Threats do not make a claim true. Threatening a man in retaliation for not accepting a claim as true, regardless of its truth value, is never a rational means of validation. In fact, threats have been identified as an ad baculum fallacy, meaning the "appeal to force." (See my fallacies page for details.)

Attempts to legitimize the tactics of the New Testament's doctrines by equivocating the concept 'threat' with the softer, less retaliatory concept 'warning', are shown to fail in the context of defending the Bible's condemnation of non-belief. See for example my article An Aborted Rise to Challenge for an example of and response to such equivocation. Objectivism holds that faith necessitates force, either physical or psychological, and that faith cannot survive without the threat of force. See Ayn Rand, "Faith and Force: The Destroyers of the Modern World," Philosophy: Who Needs It, pp. 58-76.

[8] For instance, see my critique Considering Bahnsen's Short Essay Van Til's 'Presuppositionalism'.

[9] The issue of the objective, hierarchical nature of (legitimate) knowledge and how the mystic epistemology of Christianity in particular is an attempt to derail this objective nature, will be identified and exposed in my future essay, "The Nature of Christian Knowledge."

[10] For an exposé of the error-bound cosmological root of god-belief when considering the notion 'god' in the context of a universe-creating consciousness, see my article God and Pure Self-Reference in my series Letters to a Young Atheologist.

[11] In other words, one need only affirm the Objectivist axioms, 'existence', 'identity' and 'consciousness' and recognize their proper relationship. In questions of "authority" apologists may complain that non-believers cannot prove the validity of their own minds. As one apologist once asked me, "How do you know your mind is a reliable guide?" The question amounts to: How does one justify his own consciousness? But why should this be necessary? The fact of consciousness is axiomatic: one must assume the fact that man is conscious even to question, deny or ignore it. The insistence that one should "justify" his own consciousness ignores this fact and commits those who insist on such matters to an infinite regress.

[12] While Objectivists readily acknowledge that the axioms are not subject to proofs, the axioms can be validated, which is a process broader than proof. As Dr. Leonard Peikoff notes, "'Validation'… subsumes any process of establishing an idea's relationship to reality, whether deductive reasoning, inductive reasoning, or perceptual self-evidence" (Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand, [New York: Meridian, 1993], p. 8). For an excellent demonstration of how the primacy of existence - that is, the Objectivist axioms - can be validated, see Dr. David Kelley, The Primacy of Existence, audio tape, 1985, available through Principle Source.

[13] Leonard Peikoff, "Maybe You're Wrong," The Objectivist Forum, April, 1981, p. 12.

[14] I have already touched on what I believe to be the primary motivations for religious apologetics in my essay Dear Apologist.

[15] For further discussion of what this means, see my essay The Issue of Metaphysical Primacy.

[16] See Leonard Peikoff, "Objectivity," Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand (New York: Meridian, 1993), pp. 110-151 for development of the Objectivist concept of objectivity. It should be noted that Objectivism views morality as a science rather than a code of commands, which means moral principles are to be discovered by reason, not a bill of duties received on some mountaintop in a remote region on earth and followed out of fear. Peikoff makes the point, An Introduction to Objectivism, Part 2: Q & A, that "we should have commandments in morality any more than we should in physics." See my essay The Lessons of Jesus: Imperatives Without Reason.

[17] "Introduction to Logic," lecture series (1974, Lecture 9; quoted in Glossary of Objectivist Definitions, by Ayn Rand (ed. Allison T. Kunze and Jean F. Moroney) (Gaylordsville, CT: Second Renaissance Books, 1999), s.v., 'induction'.

[18] The mysterious ingredient lurking behind Mr. Walker's intellectual aloofness here is most likely what presuppositionalists refer to as the sensus divinitatus, or the direct knowledge all human beings allegedly have of the Christian God.

[19] By 'empiricism' in this context I mean the empiricists in David Hume's skeptical tradition. For Objectivist treatment of Hume's ideas, see David Kelley's The Evidence of the Senses, (Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana State University Press, 1986), pp. 18-21, 129-130, 156-157, 172-173, et al.

[20] For some more clarification how the "non-absolute orderliness" of the universe entailed by the mystical nature of Christianity disables induction and preempts rational certainty for those who assume its truth, see my Dialogue on Induction in my Sample Dialogues section.

[21] Some may object to this definition of 'universe' as referring to "the total of existence" by claiming that it is arbitrary, even though Merriam-Webster's confirms this definition ("the whole body of things and phenomena observed or postulated"). However, such a claim would have to consider the manner in which the concept 'universe' is formed. Conceptual economy requires that we form a concept which includes all existence (i.e., all things which exist regardless of their specific nature) in its reference. Without a concept with such universal inclusion, we have no means of effectively considering and discussing universal principles. Objections against this definition of 'universe' are usually motivated by the desire to withhold some alleged (or "postulated") existent from being included in the totality, thus requiring the division of the concept "totality" or "universe" by asserting some arbitrary standard or definition which typically takes the form of a dichotomy (such as "supernatural" versus "natural," the "created order" versus the "divine," "necessary" versus "contingent," etc.), such that only the "material realm" of existence is included, while the so-called "non-material realm" (or "spiritual realm") is exempt from such reference. Any objection against the Objectivist definition of 'universe' along such lines would thus commit the fallacy of reverse-packaging, which I identify in the first of my Letters to a Young Atheology, The Issue of the Historicity of Jesus.

[22] See Mitchell's post to the Apologia list.

[23] Peikoff defines 'hierarchy of knowledge' as "a body of concepts and conclusions ranked in order of logical dependence, one upon another, according to each item's distance from the base of the structure [i.e., of one's philosophy]. The base is the perceptual data with which cognition begins." Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand, p. 131. See especially pages 129-141 of the chapter titled "Objectivity" for a more complete discussion of the Objectivist view of the hierarchical nature of knowledge and its importance to objectivity.

[24] I do not mean to suggest here that the reversal of the relationship between knowledge and emotion is the only derailment of the knowledge hierarchy to which religious philosophies commit their adherents. Indeed, there are many such instances of hierarchical reversal which result from the attempt to base one's ideas on alleged "revelations," but their root is the misprioritization of emotion over knowledge (e.g., that wishing makes something true). I explore these problems in greater detail in my upcoming essay The Roots of Christian Knowledge.

[25] In this context I refer to Christianity as any religious code which takes its fundamental inspiration from the Old and New Testaments; accepts Jesus as the "Son of God," affirms the miraculous resurrection of Jesus as evidence of the supernatural and the key to personal salvation, etc.

[26] A tangentially related question on this point would be: Are these theists Christians, or are they Van Tillians? I suspect - and this is definitely "off the cuff" - that as "reformed apologetics" continues to evolve in its arbitrary meandering, Christianity proper (however loose such a definition we must allow) will suffer the birth of yet another splinter group: the Van Tillians, a group of academics whose primary idol of worship, should they admit it or not (it's doubtful any ever will), is not the Jesus of the New Testament, but the apologist Cornelius Van Til himself. After all, there are photos of this individual, testifying to his actual existence on earth - a benefit which Jesus-believers do not have. Calling them "Reformed" would not be satisfactory. For even the "Scripturalists" - i.e., the followers of Gordon H. Clark's teachings - refer to themselves as "Reformed" as well, yet the divisions between them and those who align themselves with Van Til's views run deep and bitter. Indeed, "there be some reading here today who shall not taste of death…" till they hear a recording of Van Til himself broadcasting his convoluted arguments and cheap intellectual gimmicks to sheepish sycophants, recorded when Van Til was indoctrinating more impressionable young minds at the seminary. That is, after all, only my prediction. It may have already been fulfilled!

[27] "The Philosophy of Objectivism," lecture series (1976), question period, Lecture 2. See also The Tindrbox Files, Post 47: More Howardian Assumptions, Pt. II.

[28] I must point out my taking exception to the notion of positing the notion of "the atheist worldview," as the non-theistic critic mentions here. There is no single "atheistic worldview"; rather, there are worldviews which dispense with theism, of which Objectivism is only one.

[29] See my essay Correcting Common Errors for a discussion of the reasons why I hold that Heidegger's question "why is there something rather than nothing?" is invalid.

[30] Leonard Peikoff, "Idealism and Materialism as the Rejection of Basic Axioms," Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand, p. 31.

[31] The New Unger's Bible Dictionary, Harrison, R. K., ed., (The Moody Bible Press: Chicago, Ill., 1988), s.v., 'omniscience'.

[32] See my commentary God and Omniscience for a closer study of the incoherence of the notion 'omniscience'.

[33] See Peikoff, "The Philosophy of Objectivism," lecture series (1976), Q&A Lecture 8, quoted in "Mercy," The Ayn Rand Lexicon: Objectivism A to Z, p. 290.

[34] For a somewhat humorous, yet pointed anecdote in regard to this characteristic of the Judeo-Christian God, see An Unchanging God?

[35] That the Christian God is said to be wrathful or angry is clearly and explicitly stated in the Bible. For instance,

Numbers 11:33 states: " And while the flesh was yet between their teeth, ere it was chewed, the wrath of the LORD was kindled against the people, and the LORD smote the people with a very great plague."

Numbers 16:46 states that "there is wrath gone out from the LORD; the plague is begun."

II Kings 22:17 states (God allegedly speaking here), "Because they have forsaken me, and have burned incense unto other gods, that they might provoke me to anger with all the works of their hands; therefore my wrath shall be kindled against this place, and shall not be quenched."

In II Chronicles 28:11, we read: "Now hear me therefore, and deliver the captives again, which ye have taken captive of your brethren: for the fierce wrath of the LORD is upon you."

Clearly the poets of the Bible figured their God to be prone to the attribute of wrath, since we read in Psalm 89:46: "How long, LORD? wilt thou hide thyself for ever? shall thy wrath burn like fire?"

And in Psalm 90:7 we read (in prayer to God), "For we are consumed by thine anger, and by thy wrath are we troubled."

Indeed, the Bible has its God motivated by his wrath to dreadful action, clearly acting only on impulse. For instance, Exodus 22:24 has the biblical God state: "And my wrath shall wax hot, and I will kill you with the sword; and your wives shall be widows, and your children fatherless."

Exodus 32:10 has the biblical God state: "Now therefore let me alone, that my wrath may wax hot against them, and that I may consume them: and I will make of thee a great nation."

The biblical God is also portrayed as inclined to pin the blame of his wrath on the actions of man, for in Deuteronomy 9:7-8 we read, "Remember, and forget not, how thou provokedst the LORD thy God to wrath in the wilderness: from the day that thou didst depart out of the land of Egypt, until ye came unto this place, ye have been rebellious against the LORD. Also in Horeb ye provoked the LORD to wrath, so that the LORD was angry with you to have destroyed you." Poor Horeb, how horrible was his fate!

And again in Deuteronomy 9, verse 22, we read, "And at Taberah, and at Massah, and at Kibrothhattaavah, ye provoked the LORD to wrath."

Given these, and many, many more similar verses throughout the Bible, it is indisputable that wrath is an attribute of the biblical God. More examples of the Bible's wrath-drenched, anger-driven God can be found by searching the Bible Gateway using search words like 'wrath' and 'anger', etc. I found 197 results when I searched the King James Version under the word 'wrath' (compared with only three instances of the word 'smile' and six instances of 'happiness'!). A large proportion of these results attribute this character trait to the biblical God, while others are descriptions of men, for whom angry emotions are natural.

Incidentally, if God is said to be "immutable" - i.e., that he does not change, then God must be eternally wrathful (and therefore hopelessly miserable), for otherwise, if God's wrath is excitable and quenchable, then this would infer that God has the capacity to change, and this would contradict aforementioned attributes of God.

[36] See my essay Why an Immortal Being Cannot Value.

[37] Many will object to the use of the term 'scheming' in this context because of its negative connotation. But such negative connotation is appropriate to the context, according to Christianity's own primary source, the Bible. For instance, Ezekiel 14:9 states: "And if the prophet be deceived when he hath spoken a thing, I the Lord have deceived that prophet, and I will stretch out my hand upon him, and will destroy him from the midst of my people Israel." If this kind of deliberate divine deceit is not rightly characterized as scheming, what is?

[38] On this note, I would point to the passages in the first chapters of Genesis which portray God as a creator of "earth and heaven" (as if they needed a creator). See also the scriptural supports given for item [i] "omnipotent" above.

[39] See footnote [35] to item [l] "wrathful" above.

[40] These points are elaborated elsewhere. For an overview, see my Atheological Credo and my correspondence Religion Wears a Bloody Glove and my essay The Issue of Metaphysical Primacy. Off-site see Chapter 9: Religion from David King's Guide to Objectivism. Recommended audio tapes include: Andrew Bernstein's 5-tape series The Primacy of Consciousness Versus the Objectivist Ethics (1994); John Ridpath's Religion Versus Man (1989; two tapes), and his Religion and Capitalism (1998; two tapes); and Leonard Peikoff's excellent speech Religion Versus America (1986; one tape). Audio recordings of these lectures are available at Second Renaissance Books.

[41] Taken from Russell Stewart's Why I Believe That Evolution is True.

[42] See http://www.ccir.ed.ac.uk/~jad/vantil-list/archive-May-2000/msg00037.html

[43] See my anecdote An Unchanging God? to see why the conclusion that the Christian God, as defined by defenders of this notion, assuming it exists, must be a deeply miserable being.

© Copyright by Anton Thorn 2002. All rights reserved.

 

[Back to Thorn's Morgue]

[Back to Anton Thorn's Main Page]

[Back to Top]

Completed and posted [date] - ATOA