The Resurrection Story Revisited

 

 

The proceeding correspondence is a follow-up to my article More on the Resurrection Tale, which itself was a follow-up to my original A Query on the Resurrection.

 

Mr. ____ writes:

Well, you caught me in my haste and carelessness. I forgot to answer your challenges. sorry. when I first emailed you I did wonder if I was being ambition. You seem to produce quite long arguments, and I have sever time constraints. Also, you are unquestionably my superior in debate. I do not concede that my arguments are wrong, but I do concede that you're more skilled at arguing then I. HOwever, that's not what this is about. This isn't a debate where judges score us and one wins or loses. This is a search for the truth, and a search for the best way to live life.

Thorn:

The only advise I can offer here is, check your premises and be ready to defend your ideas. If you assert something as truth, and others do not accept what you say, choose your method: reason, or non-reason. You want me to believe that event X happened even though your methodology of accepting this allegation as true is epistemologically suspicious, and the content of what you claim is itself suspicious and not without unanswered questions. The questions are pending, the answers are empty, and my reasons for rejecting the claims of the resurrection of Jesus are sound.

You have come to me with the challenge to disprove the tale of the resurrection. I retort that I have no obligation to do so, simply because I do not accept it as knowledge. However, you do accept this claim as knowledge, yet you want me to accept the onus of disproving it, even before you offer a proof (which you still have not done). These facts alone betray your subjective bias in favor of the ideas in question. What justifies this bias? You do not say.

Anyhow, even though I do not accept the presumption that I bear some kind of onus to disprove the resurrection simply because I do not accept it as knowledge, I do offer you the tools by which I demonstrate why such a claim can be dismissed as invalid. I offered you the law of identity, and the basis on which it is founded, the very basis which you must take for granted yourself, even if your intention is to dispute or nullify it. You have basically acknowledged this fact in your subsequent correspondence.

Furthermore, not only have you failed to raise any enduring doubt or criticism against the absolute validity of the law of identity, you fail to offer an alternative basis on which to anchor any alternative course of reasoning which ostensively validates such claims as that of the resurrection of Christ. You want the conclusion, but you won't identify the conclusions roots. Why is that? You do not say.

Next I offer you two counter-challenges:

  1. Demonstrate the power of faith, an alleged power which many Christians before you have proclaimed; and
  2. Name one eyewitness to the resurrection. Instead of accepting these challenges, you weasel out of them with doubletalk. Doubletalk is expressive of the wish to have your cake, and to eat it, too. It is suspicious for a reason, just as it is true that, when there is smoke, there is usually fire.

You take the offensive by approaching me with your challenges. I show that I have no obligation to meet them, but do so anyway. I offer you challenges in return, and you evade them. But still you take issue with me for not accepting your god-belief claims.

What justifies this behavior?

Why do you want me to believe your claims so badly anyway? What is in it for you? If you say you are not motivated by selfish reasons, then by what reasons are you motivated? You obviously want me to believe your claims for some reason, don't you? Or, is it that you want me to believe them for no reason? Something has to give, Mr. ____, and this is it. You're going to have to start looking inward to yourself to answer these questions. I don't think you need to correspond with me to sort your own mind out. You need to start being honest with yourself. You either do believe, or you pretend to believe, what you claim you believe, for some reason. What is that reason? Why is it so obscured? What is it being hidden under the believer's reluctance to talk about method? Does his method not have an identity? Is it a method which he thinks I won't accept, and therefore decides not to embarrass himself by showing it to me anyway?

If I made the claim to you that a superwonderbeing named Blarko existed in the beyond world, and that Blarko was both a far away being as well as an up close and personal fuzzy pal, who could be your closest buddy, and do anything you ask in his name, what would you tell me? Would you tell me that you believe me, and that you think Blarko exists as well? Or, would you expect that I should produce some evidence for my claim before you believe it yourself? If you expect that I should produce some evidence, then why are you not willing to produce some evidence for your claims? If not, then why not believe right now, with all your soul and all your might, that Blarko exists, that Blarko is near, that Blarko does not need to be far? Blarko wants you to believe in Him. Blarko fashioned you out of cosmic silk, and lined you with consciousness. Blarko wants you to simply cozy on up to your lining, and He will meet you there, and you could both snuggle. Why don’t you accept this? Why do you resist this? Why are you afraid of such intimacy with that which is so far beyond your comprehension?

See, the table can be turned on you as well, if I wanted to pursue the arbitrary in contradistinction to your arbitrary. How would you fight it? How would you undo it? How would you dispel its illusions? If your own basis were just as arbitrary as that of your opponent, your position will fare no better than his, so long as he is consistent with his. But what guarantees consistency? Already, we need the law of identity, even in order to conjure up the arbitrary. Why? Because we can contrast what is real against what we imagine and project mentally. We do this all day long. I plan to go to bed later this evening; that is projecting into the future. I imagine that I will be tired, but only reality will confirm or disconfirm this projection.

 

Mr. ____ writes:

I overlooked the one challenge in reading your argument, and the other in countering it. My apologies. In answer to your first challenge, I don't have faith as a mustard seed. I don't claim to. That's a lot of faith my friend.

Thorn:

I have no idea how much faith is supposed to equal a mustard seed's worth of faith. The passages in which this metaphor is given make it out to sound like it's not a lot of faith, since it is supposedly compared to "the least of all seeds" (cf. Matt. 13:31-32). But we find that Jesus was even wrong here, for seeds from the poppy family are even smaller than those of the mustard family (I've seen a lot of sorry attempts to wriggle out of this problem, but they're all just as laughable as other apologetic evasions). But if this is more faith than you have, so be it. It's certainly more faith than I have, so perhaps we're a lot more alike than you want to admit. (Maybe that's the source of your fear?)

The bottom line here is, however, is the fact that you cannot meet my challenge to demonstrate the supposed power of faith. Sadly, the same is true for every Christian I have ever met. Why do you suppose that is?

Mr. ____ writes:

Also, think of this from God's perspective. He sent his son to die on the cross for you, and you tell him that you won't believe him until he does a trick so that you can see it. Sound reasonable to you?

Thorn:

The Bible boasts great power as a result of believing its garbage. Modern Christians repeat these boastings. I simply ask for a demonstration, and one never comes. If I made some boastful claim to some extraordinary power, but could never seem to come through with a demonstration of that alleged power, would you still believe me anyway, in spite of the lousy excuses that are offered to evade meeting that challenge? Or, do you expect that people should just accept such claims uncritically, without proof, against their own sound reasoning to the opposite? If so, why? If not, then what's the fuss?

Mr. ____ write:

Now then, naming a witness. There was not a man who watched Jesus die on the cross, was able to check his pulse and what have you, then followed him into the tomb, sat there for 3 days, and was there watching when he came back to life.

Thorn:

That's right. There were no witnesses at all to the resurrection. No one saw Jesus actually rise from the dead. Enough now with any talk of all the eyewitnesses of the resurrection. There are none supplied by the gospels.

This is a sad but irrevocably devastating blow to all the apologetic mantras asserting eyewitness testimony to substantiate the claim of Jesus' resurrection. It's no wonder that apologists would rather trivialize this fact when it is pointed out to them.

Mr. ____ writes:

However, a number of people saw him die, and the Roman centurion confirmed to Pilate that he was daid, and then the apostles and many others saw him living several days after he allegedly died.

Thorn:

Exactly, we are expected to accept the inference of anonymous men, men whose character we never have the benefit of examining, who could have believed all kinds of assorted, wild folk tales, as recorded by anonymous men whose characters again we cannot examine. But not only are we expected to accept these inferences, we are to make these inferences central to our lives, to allow these inferences, which are not based on any eyewitness testimony, but upon hearsay and embellishment, to direct our choices and actions in life, even though they go against objectivity. If your life and mind is so worthless to you that this is good enough to guide your life, so be it. But why the surprise and desperation when others do not consider their minds and lives so worthless as to accept such folly as so important in life?

But let's examine this a bit further, this time with a little more critical thinking.

On the reliability of the supposed witness of Jesus' death, Richard Carrier notes:

[Josh] McDowell, citing Michael Green, also very strangely thinks that this hearing of Jesus cry out counts as proof he was dead (1st ed., p. 198; § 10.4A.1B.1C; 2nd ed., p. 223, § 9.6A.1B.1C). It is a good thing modern doctors do not announce someone's death on such evidence! McDowell cites Green and E.H. Day in the same place as asserting that the Roman soldiers at the crucifixion were "specialists" in assessing death, though that is a bit silly. Seeing people die does not make one a medical expert, nor does being an expert in killing people result in the discovery of how to check a pulse or touch the eye or apply any other technique that is necessary to reliably check someone for life who appears to be dead. After movies and TV educated the public, the idea of checking a pulse, for instance, has become common knowledge (and mass novels in the 19th century spread the word somewhat), but in antiquity only an elite few even knew of such a thing. So there is absolutely no reason to believe that common soldiers even knew what a pulse was, much less how to check one--and certainly, we hear of no such detailed examination: the accounts we have explicitly deny it by asserting that Jesus was declared dead before he was even taken down. If we reject the accounts as false, we have nothing left to show that survival was less likely--we become completely ignorant of what really happened that day. (How Do We Know Jesus Was Dead?)

Read that one sentence again: "the accounts we have explicitly deny [any possibility that the soldiers could have checked Jesus' pulse, etc.] by asserting that Jesus was declared dead before he was even taken down" from the cross. Is it not possible that the diagnosis of Jesus' death was premature, even if we grant all the events recorded in the gospels as accurate? Certainly, it is very possible.

Carrier notes that misdiagnosis of death is not impossible:

Being mistaken for dead is not impossible. Ancient accounts of misdiagnosed deaths exist. Pliny the Elder, writing in the 60's and 70's AD, collects several of them in his Natural History (7.176-179): people who were deemed dead, observed as dead all through their funeral, and on the pyre, ready to be set aflame, but who walked away nonetheless. One account includes a wound that would seem almost certainly fatal (a cut throat, 7.176). Alexander the Great himself was impaled by a spear, which punctured one of his lungs, yet he recovered. Even modern accounts of misdiagnosed deaths exist, proving that even medical experts can be in error: as recently as 1989 in Springfield, Ohio (cf. St. Louis Post-Dispatch, Aug. 17, pg. 2A) and 1994 in San Leandro, California (Orlando Sentinel, Jan. 29, pg. A20). (Ibid.)

If misdiagnosis of death is possible in modern times, in spite of our unique benefits made available by our advances in science and medicine, how much more possible was misdiagnosis in ancient times in primitive cultures lacking these benefits?

Carrier asks:

What are the odds that Jesus was misdiagnosed as dead? As it is, we must grant at least a 10% chance that the centurion mistook him for dead, and that is granting him an excellent diagnostic skill, especially to assess this at a distance as the story says he did. If Jesus was drugged, this chance would certainly have to rise to at least a 50% chance, for how would a centurion know anything of the possible effects of drugs, much less that they had been administered? As far as he knew, the sponge was soaked in vinegar. (Ibid.)

Indeed, how would any centurions know if Jesus had been drugged? I don't think they would have known. How can we be certain that the authors of the gospels were not mistaken about the substance or substances which were contained in the mysterious sponge? It could very well be the case that the oral tradition from which the authors elaborated their gospel stories was mistaken about the mysterious sponge, but it got recorded as history anyway. How do you know? How can you be so certain of this? Were you there? No. Why are you willing to reject the law of identity in favor of these tales?

Mr. ____ writes:

The Bible, in the words of my social studies teacher, "is as much a history book as anything".

Thorn:

I don't have a problem with this at all. Indeed, in a sense I agree. The Bible is certainly to be considered a history book in the sense that it records what a budding culture believed. But that does not mean that all of its contents are true. In other words, it is the very nature of its content as a history book which calls itself into question. It does not follow from the fact that we have documents reporting what some people believed to have happened at one time before their lives, that those things actually happened the way that they're described. It is a non sequitur to say, "we have documents that X believed Y happened, therefore Y must have happened the way X says it did," particularly when those documents call themselves into question.

In response to your social studies teacher, I say: So what?

 

Mr. ____ writes:

These people spouted historical facts.

Thorn:

That is the claim you are asked to prove. So far, you've not proved merit to this claim. Repeating this statement only begs the question.

Mr. ____ writes:

You have raised some examples of cotradictions to that, but the Bible has prevailed over such objections in the past and I trust will again.

Thorn:

Correction: The supposed veracity of the Bible has not prevailed over the objections; the law of identity cannot be mocked. What has prevailed is some people's belief that the Bible is true in its every claim. That's not the same thing that you are asserting here. We must discount the law of identity in order to accept the miracle claims of the Bible; this I have already established, and in one of your messages your response to this was that God could "bend" the law of identity at will. This is the primacy of consciousness view of reality, and Objectivism shows why this is invalid (see my website).

If this is the course you want to take, you are making a statement about the dullness of your own mind, not about the supposed truth of the Bible's claims.

Mr. ____ writes:

I can't give you video tapes of the resurrection, or any such thing, but the bible has multiple accounts of the resurrection.

Thorn:

This gets you no further, particularly if we recognize that the gospels were dramatizations increasing in elaboration and embellishment as the traditions of the Jesus cult were spread. Some of the essays I linked to on my first response to you shed some light on these topics, and refer to further articles of relevant interest. Did you read any of those essays? Did you really study them? Or, did you just breeze over them (if that), and ignore their points?

 

Mr. ____ writes:

Also, the gospel writers didn't seem to be insane, or any such thing.

Thorn:

Well, we don't have much to go on in determining the character of the men who authored the gospels. We don't even know who they were. And we don't know the character of the men from whom the gospel writers got their stories. So whether they were insane or not may never be known; it is all forgotten in history, and we don’t have the detail necessary to make a solid determination in this regard.

However, it could very well be that the gospel writers were religiously hypnotized people. Look at the antics you see in some charismatic churches today. I have watched believers gyrate themselves silly into deep, hypnotic-like trances as they shake and shuffle to organ music and a chorus of handclaps as they were summoned by the altar call. Some have even collapsed to the ground speaking gibberish (so-called "speaking in tongues") as their bodies wiggle violently on the ground. Some take such episodic fits as "evidence" of God's "moving" in that person's body and life. To me, this is evidence of the mind-game of the evangelical mind-control system of the Bible. Either way, it is mysticism through and through.

While it is certainly the case that we have little to go on in sizing up the character of the individuals who originally authored the gospel accounts and other New Testament writings, we do have some clue as to the kind of character of those who later compiled and ratified the canon of the New Testament. Start with Carrier's introduction on this topic, The Formation of the New Testament Canon. Did you know that the books of the Bible were assembled according to popular vote? Most Sunday Christians never learn this fact, and most tutored apologists ignore or dismiss this fact as trivial or irrelevant. And who were the individuals who were involved in this vote? What were they like? Were they men of solid integrity? Not by the loosest definition of the word!

Mr. ____ writes:

and for a while in Rome their recounting of these ludicrous sounding tales like Jesus being resurrected, something which you want to allege was a conspiracy or something they made up, could have gotten them killed, and in some cases did. Would you risk your life to convince children of the truth of Greek mythology, which you don't believe yourself?

Thorn:

First of all, it is not a question of my wanting "to allege" that the tale of Jesus' resurrection was a conspiracy. It is a question of putting the tattered, inconsistent and vague pieces of "evidence" together to see what might have taken place, if we grant any credibility to the gospel tales to begin with. So far, you've offered no reason why one should grant such credibility, and I cannot think of any defender of the Christian faith who has made a convincing case that we should grant this credibility to the accounts in the New Testament. In this regard, I've given you an enormous amount of slack and benefit of the doubt, and still you fumble your opportunity to present any proof of the resurrection or of the alleged power of 'faith in God'. Meanwhile, I'm off enjoying my life as I determine fit, and you're stuck, your king checkmated at every turn.

As for people risking their lives for dubious faith claims… Do you really believe that someone risking his or her life for some alleged truth is sufficient evidence to determine that alleged truth to be in fact genuinely representative of reality? What about the kamikaze pilots of WWII? Do you know about them? They believed that Emperor Hirohito of Japan was a god, and they certainly were more than willing to die for this alleged truth. But does this convince you that Hirohito was in fact a god? How could it? At the end of the war, as part of Japan's surrender to the West, Hirohito renounced his claim to divine status. If all those kamikaze pilots committed suicide for a lie - and they surely did, why is it not possible that alleged Christian martyrs (who are mentioned but rarely named) similarly died for a lie? A particularly relevant essay which you might find interesting is Mako Sasaki's Who Became Kamikaze Pilots, and How Did They Feel Towards Their Suicide Mission?

In the end, the appeal to martyrs is nothing but an appeal to emotions. It does not matter how many people die for the supposed truth of religious claims. The fact that someone allows himself to be martyred or kills himself does not make his beliefs true. Likewise, killing others does not make one's beliefs true. Indeed, if something is true, what can be gained by one's death? If it is true, it is already true, and one's death is irrelevant. And just as Christians have their lists of "martyred saints," so do other rival religions.

Again, so what?

People considering religious beliefs should not be concerned with how many people believed those things before them, or how many people allegedly "died for" those beliefs. Instead, they should consider whether or not those beliefs are true. These are two completely different matters, and today's believers would do well to abandon this fallacy-drenched approach to apologetics. It gets them nowhere and just makes themselves look all the more foolish.

Besides, exactly how does someone dying prove any one faith claim at the exclusion of another? That's the whole thing about faith claims: they are deliberately malleable so that they can be applied to virtually any context in some self-reaffirming manner which seems plausible to those who are already persuaded by them.

Mr. ____ writes:

There are a number of books of antiquity which you believe the truth of, right? There's an interesting chart in Don't check your brains at the door. It compares the new testament with the writings of Caesar, Sophocles, Thucydides, Plato, Catullus, Euripides, and Aristotle. Those works were written in a range from 496 to 44 BC, allegedly. The earliest copies we have of them are dated 944 to 1600 years after their alleged writing, roughly. the number of copies written around then that we have range from 3 to 100. The new testament, on the other hand, was written from 40 to 100 AD, the most ancient known copies date to 125 AD, and the number of copies found from around that time is over 25000. Yet you would trust those things stated as facts in the Greek and Roman works, but not those stated as facts in the new testament.

Thorn:

All this misses the point completely. The number of copies of a particular text cannot substitute for a validation of the content contained in those copies, whether they number 3, 100 or more than 25,000. If something is in error and it is copied, the error is merely duplicated, not corrected. This approach to defending Christian claims is about as flimsy as a defense can get, and only exposes the believers' desperation to turn anything into some kind of plausible argument on behalf of their beliefs.

Furthermore, it may very well be the case that I think many books of antiquity contain some truth. If the content has some evidence in its favor, is internally consistent, and is consistent with previously validated knowledge (such as - at the very least! - the law of identity), then obviously some argument can be made in behalf of its alleged truth. The mystical content of the Bible and many other books of the antiquity do not meet these simple criteria.

Again, I turn to Carrier's abbreviated version of Why I Don't Buy the Resurrection Story, in which he writes:

In 520 A.D. an anonymous monk recorded the life of Saint Genevieve, who had died only ten years previous. In his account of her life, he describes how, when she ordered a cursed tree cut down, monsters sprung from it and breathed a fatal stench on many men for two hours; while she was sailing, eleven ships capsized, but at her prayers they were righted again spontaneously; she cast out demons, calmed storms, miraculously created water and oil from nothing before astonished crowds, healed the blind and lame, and several people who stole things from her actually went blind instead. No one wrote anything to contradict or challenge these claims, and they were written very near the time the events supposedly happened--by a religious man whom we suppose regarded lying to be a sin. Yet do we believe any of it? Not really. And we shouldn't

Do you accept the claims about Saint Genevieve as wholly true? If not, why not?

(Readers may also want to read Michael A. Turton's The Christ of Doaist Alchemy for some enlightenment on the extremely well documented miracle claims of Chinese mystic adepts contemporaneous to 1st century Palestine. It is doubtful that today's Christian believers will regard these miracle stories as divinely authentic as well.)

Furthermore, in regard to the content of the books of antiquity to which I am willing to grant credibility, there is one more blatant error in any proposed analogy between that content and the content of supposed "holy books" like the Bible which apologists attempt to construct in defense of their Christian god-beliefs. And that error is: While I may grant that some of the content in those books of antiquity may be true, that content is not a primary, nor does it provide the foundation of my view of reality. Christians want to say that, if I accept something claimed to have been written by Aristotle or Plato as true, both of whom predated the time of Jesus, then I should also grant the supposed truth of the New Testament. Why? "Because we have so many copies!" they will claim. This apologetic approach attempts to carry itself on the seemingly innocuous commonality between the secular books of antiquity and the writings of the budding Christ cult. But where the secular books of antiquity are presented as the writings of mere men and no more, the writings of the Christ cult are presented under the pretense that they were authored by a supernatural, universe-creating, reality-ruling being, a God. And where some secular books of antiquity offer considered philosophical inquiry and sometimes discourse (so-called peripatetic or dialogical reasoning), the writings of the Christ cult offer hysteria and absurdity. Any attempt therefore to foist some analogy here is consequently weakened to a significant degree, indeed at the expense of the reputation of the apologist's intellect.

Furthermore, as George H. Smith points out in his classic Atheism: The Case Against God,

In assessing the ethical significance of Jesus, it is illuminating to contrast him with the ancient Greek philosophers who preceded him by hundreds of years. The differences are so striking that few scholars care to place Jesus on the same level as such intellectual giants as Plato and Aristotle. Whether one agrees with these philosophers or not, they at least argue for their claims; Jesus, on the other hand, issues proclamations backed by the threat of force. (p. 321.)

Even in methodology, if Jesus could be said to have taught according to some kind of method, the differences between the philosophers of antiquity and Jesus are, as Smith says, "striking."

Mr. ____ writes:

Do you believe everything to be absolute?

Thorn:

What relevance does this question have to your being able to prove the claim that Jesus rose from the dead? Why does the focus of your inquiry concentrate so much on what I believe? I think you know what I hold to be true about reality. Your focus should not be what I believe, but rather what you believe and why. So far, if you have any substantial, non-flimsy reasoning to back up your claim that Jesus died on the cross and rose a few days later, you've not presented it.

Mr. ____ writes:

I do in the sense that there must be some absolute truth out there, and I'm pretty confident I know what it is, but I'm not confident that I'll know that thing to be absolutely true.

Thorn:

Then why do you take issue with me when I've presented a solid, impenetrable case against believing the resurrection tale to be true, when you yourself admit that you're "not confident that [you'll] know that thing to be absolutely true"? You have a lot of questions which you should be asking yourself, not me. I already know why I hold as true what I hold as true. You seem at best confused on fundamentals.

Mr. ____ writes:

You deride me for creating assorted worlds in which we live in an illusion, because for such a thing to be that way A must be A.

Thorn:

You're caricaturing our correspondence here. For one thing, I do not deride you. Rather, I implore you to consider your own claims and your reasoning about those claims with a greater degree of critical thought. Also, I do not believe you have been "creating assorted worlds in which we live in an illusion." I think you are referring here to the scenarios you provided as examples to illustrate your points. I showed why those scenarios themselves had to assume the law of identity in order to make sense to begin with, which was the very principle they were intended to dismantle. I showed how your reasoning was flawed. This was not meant as derision. After all, I think you've learned something from corresponding with me, haven't you?

Mr. ____ writes:

Obviously I can't express myself without the assumption that A is A, but I don't claim to have unlocked even that seemingly basic law of the universe.

Thorn:

That's just the point: the law of identity is not "locked" to begin with. It is not something which is 'revealed' to some men and not to others. If the law of identity, its meaning or its fundamentality is shrouded in mystery to you, then you have not grasped the nature of axiomatic concepts. For this, I refer you to Ayn Rand's Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology and to Leonard Peikoff's Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand.

Mr. ____ writes:

I don't claim to know it for sure. I'm very bad at thinking outside of my "humn box", so to speak. I wondered how I'd explain hearing to a deaf person, and I immediately began "I would _say_". I don't claim that A being A must be true simply because that's the only way I can understand things.

Thorn:

The truth of the law of identity is not based on our apprehension of it. If that were the case, we could choose not to apprehend it, and its truth would thereby be disabled. Again, see the sources I mentioned above.

Mr. ____ writes:

You say that demolishing confidence in reality and reasoning is what religion is all about. Sorry if I keep referring to DOn't check your brains at the door, but I seem to have cleverly misplaced my other resources. In nay event, the title "don't check your brains at the door" is a counter to that statement.

Thorn:

If it is true that the title of McDowell's cheap paperback is "a counter" to my contention that religion preys on disestablishing men's confidence in reality, then McDowell obviously commits a performative inconsistency in naming his book.

Mr. ____ writes:

Let me ask you this, Anton. Why have brilliant men and women, firm atheists, of the past often set out to disprove christianity only to become a christian? Did they go insane? Did some Christian beat down their resistance? Don't tell me that they lacked objectivism and that was their weakness. objectivism is an interesting philosophy, but I don't see it as the only way to be an atheist. There are several examples of brilliant people who became christians though they were originally Atheists. I named a few in my last letter, now I'll name a few better known ones. CS Lewis. Lew wallace. Frank Morison. The latter two became christians while working on disproving christianity. Brilliant men, all.

Thorn:

I don't see this as a matter of atheism vs. Christianity or theism so much as I see this as a matter of the primacy of existence vs. the primacy of consciousness. Many people are atheists but at the same time accept the primacy of consciousness view of reality in some facet of their thinking. While it may be the case that the individuals you mention were "brilliant men," this is ultimately irrelevant. Just because one is thought to be brilliant does not mean his every conclusion is sound or his reasoning about his every conclusion is infallible. Our conclusions are only as sound as our starting points, and no more. If the foundations of our reasoning is questionable, what happens to the end product of that reasoning? Do we hold that those conclusions are sound simply because we want to agree with those conclusions?

You warn me that I not answer that their problem was "that they lacked objectivism and that was their weakness." But that indeed is the problem, in a nutshell. A you yourself state, Objectivism is not "the only way to be an atheist," and I agree. Atheism as such is not a single, universal code of belief; rather, it is the lack of a particular kind of belief, and therefore leaves open what one does affirm as positively true about reality. That is why I state above that I see this more as a matter of the primacy of existence vs. the primacy of consciousness view of reality rather than an issue of atheism vs. theism per se. I do not have the benefit of being able to review these men's respective homework while they were still professing atheists, homework which would lay bare what they considered fundamental, what they took for granted, which premises they assumed but did not examine. Certainly, the works that they wrote after they converted to the Christian god-belief is available, such as many of C. S. Lewis' books. But these do not help, for at this point we already know what they believe. The question is what did they believe before they became Christians, and how well fortified was that knowledge?

Besides, this approach to defending one's god-belief notions ignores the fact that all men start out as atheists. No man is born with a god-belief already pre-packaged in his mind; any argument to this end will commit the fallacy of the stolen concept and is therefore unsound. So conversion from atheism to Christianity is nothing novel; indeed, it is expected in the case of believers.

Additionally, such points as you bring up here also fails to mention the many, many testimonies of former believers who later became atheists. I myself am such an example. I can name many whom I know personally who were long-time believers in the Christian cult only later to see it for what it is: genuine artificial hokum. Consider the personal testimony of atheologists Dan Barker and Farrell Till, both of whom were not only believers, but preachers of Christianity! Read some selections from Barker's book Losing Faith in Faith: From Preacher to Atheist. While Barker was in the ministry for many years, and, to the utter disappointment of his friends, parents, family, wife, and business colleagues, he admitted that it was all a lie that he had been trying to get others to believe. Later he helped found the Freedom from Religion Foundation. Farrell Till was himself in the ministry for 30 years before renouncing his faith, and is now editor of The Skeptical Review online magazine.

Other believer-to-atheist or believer-to-skeptic stories are available. For instance, Edward Babinski collected and edited a large volume of personal accounts of former believers, called Leaving the Fold: Testimonies of Former Fundamentalists (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 1995; 454 pages plus index). Babinski's own autobiographical Brief Testimony from an Ex-Christian is available online for you to read yourself.

The point is, Dan, for every non-believer-to-believer story you can give me, I can match with a believer-to-non-believer story in return. On that account, we would be even, for all we've done is match testimony with opposing testimony. But personal stories do not substitute our need for principled reasoning, and that is why my website focuses on issues of fundamental philosophical import rather than one events in particular individuals' lives. These latter are certainly instructive, but they are ultimately meaningless without the other. And so far, you have offered no principles of fundamental philosophical importance which even hints at establishing the supposed truth of your god-beliefs.

Mr. ____ writes:

What do I mean by saying that we seem to exist? simply that we do.

Thorn:

Then why use the word 'seem'?

Mr. ____ writes:

with nothing else to go on except what I perceive, I will live my life based on that.

Thorn:

But Paul claimed that Christians should "walk by faith, not by sight." (II Cor. 5:7) Paul never exhorted his believing audiences to base their thinking on what they perceived.

Mr. ____ writes:

So what's so unlikely about there being a god? the fact that Anton Thorn can't see it? have you seen a quasar? no, no one has, but you believe them to exist. The point I'm trying to make is "what's so unlikely about there being a god".

Thorn:

This statement only clarifies that you are dramatically unfamiliar with my atheology. To remedy this, start reading. You might want to start with my Atheological Credo. I suggest you read it very carefully and consult the sources I cite, both online and offline. That is, if you really want an answer to your question "what's so unlikely about there being a god?"

Mr. ____ writes:

You say that I deviate from early church fathers in striving to be logical. I don't think the apostles ever meant their work to be something that you couldn't in any way, shape, or form justify, but you should follow anyway. That would beg the simple question "why?"

Thorn:

Well, for one thing, I did cite the source (Tertullian's comment) which proved to be at variance with your approach in my second response to you. So I have backed up my contention with an authentic quotation from one of Christianity's earliest churchmen. You say that you "don't think the apostles ever meant their work to be something that you couldn't in any way, shape or form justify, but you should follow anyway." This is quite speculative on your part. For one thing, it is not my contention that believers cannot "in any way, shape, or form justify" their beliefs; rather, my contention is that they cannot justify their beliefs rationally. One could claim that Jesus' resurrection story is true because he "just knows" it to be the case; in some people's minds, this constitutes a "valid" justification (even though such a position commits the fallacy of the stolen concept).

The Bible's admittedly preferred epistemology is 'faith', which in some passages Paul equated to 'hope'. (cf. Romans 8:24). But how does hoping that something is true make it in fact true? This is never explained or demonstrated. See in particular footnote #5 of my essay Dear Apologist.

And exactly why is faith necessary if something is so gravitationally true? Indeed, this is essentially what I ask in my correspondence with another believer who took issue with my atheism. You can see a record of my correspondence with this individual in the series Kicking Against the Pricks (which my correspondence with you is rapidly starting to resemble).

In the third installment of this correspondence series, called Deconstructing Faith, you'll see that I don't hesitate to take an aggressive approach to the subject of faith. In that installment, I pose the following questions to those who affirm faith claims (such as yourself):

You mentioned above "that is the nature of faith." Can you tell me a little more about the "nature of faith"? I have a few questions:

You posit a "higher level of conscious existence" which you suggest can only be accepted on the grounds of faith. Correct? Indeed, you offer no rational argument or make any objective reference to reality in support of this assertion. This apparently does not disturb you, that your own rational processes are retired when it comes to accepting such allegations.

But what I ask is: Is this allegation true because you have faith? In other words, does it follow from the fact that you accept such an allegation as knowledge on faith, that such an allegation must therefore be true? Yes or no? Why or why not?

Or:

Do you have faith because you have determined this allegation to be true? In other words, is your acceptance of this allegation warranted by an instance of successfully testing this allegation against the facts of reality and measuring its agreement with these known facts? Yes or no? Why or why not? If yes, please document this process by first identifying your starting points and the reasoning which achieves these conclusions. In other words, please explain how you determined this to be true.

Or:

Is there another alternative which has not been covered so far? Such as: "I know of no indisputable facts of objective reality that support the conclusion that there is a 'higher level of conscious existence beyond my current ability to perceive,' but this does not matter to me, I accept it as knowledge in spite of the fact that rational support for this assertion is absent." Does this describe your position, Mr. X? I am merely attempting to understand "the nature of faith," as you put it yourself above. Can you help me here?

These questions seem fairly straightforward to me, and should be direct enough for those who expect me to accept their faith claims to address. So far, however, no one's attempted to respond to them, including the fellow to whom I originally posed them. What are your thoughts in response to them?

As for begging the question, many apologists do not hesitate any more to admit that their arguments ultimately beg the question, as the brief Presuppositionalist Circularities demonstrates. These apologists, however, actually try to make it look like question-begging arguments are a virtue when summoned to establish their preferred conclusions, but a vice when detected in support of conclusions which conflict with those preferred conclusions. Some people try to get very crafty with apologetics. Or should they be called "appall-ogetics"?

Mr. ____ writes:

well, that about covers it. Thanks for spending all this time on me. I'ts understandable that you didn't have time to respond to them all, but I do hope you read and considered them. I'm sorry about all the time it took me to get this back to you, but you remember high school, don't you? There is much to do, particularly if I want to get into a good college and what not.

Thorn:

Well, I agree, that should about cover it. But for some reason - call it experience, I suspect you'll be back again to me, charging at me with your challenges in reply, like the philosophical counterpart to a mad Mohammedan charging across the Arab desert with a primitive rifle clutched in your hands. "For the glory of God" you both shout in unison. What is it you hope to accomplish, Dan? Could it be that you're anxious to find some way around my reasoning, some Achilles' heel that you can cease on and start to scrape? Well, if you think my position has some vulnerability, then by all means find it, I'd like to know about it myself.

You don't need to apologize for the time I've spent in corresponding with you. I do so at my own choice, and for any time it takes from other things in my life (like now, I should be retired by now this time of night), I have only myself to blame. Besides, you're a fun sparring partner, and you bring up a variety of points that are fun for me to consider. And I think you may be enjoying this as well, and therefore getting something personal out of our correspondence - not just from reading my responses to you, but primarily in your own thinking experiences on these matters. You want to defend a position in which you admittedly have some reservations, possibly even some doubts of your own. Perhaps you fear compromising your beliefs, such as your belief that Jesus rose from the dead, and you believe that charging out against those who do not accept the same beliefs as you will serve to strengthen your faith in those beliefs. Many have spent long, arduous and ultimately very unfulfilling lives struggling in such an endeavor, constantly trying to evade their own guilt for accepting a steady stream of irresolvably conflicting ideas. The Bible teaches that the believer's intellectual starting point is not God, but the believer's own fears (Prov. 1:7). So in order to believe you must first admit this irrational, fundamental fear which you accept as an irreducible primary, when in fact no emotion is fundamental and irreducibly primary. But this is the point that is never truly recognized so long as one's attempting to defend its schemes. And those schemes intertwined with internal conflicts are deliberately set up to keep your mind occupied, to busy the focus of your consciousness, not on the fundamentals, but on the peripherals, such as the alleged resurrection of Jesus. This ploy - a strategy of starting you off in a race with your shoelaces tied between your shoes, and training your eyes on some finish line far off in the distance so that you never look down and see that you're about to trip really hard - has proved so successful in Christianity that it has not only flourished in entire schools of thought (many of which are in complete, even bitter conflict with each other), it has also turned out to be a form of big business, if we can imagine such a perversion (and unfortunately, we have an enormous example so that we can imagine it). Soon as the shot is fired, you launch into your race. Your eyes are so focused on the finish line that you don't even realize that you've stumbled and fallen right on your face. You never let yourself doubt - or admit that you let yourself doubt - for a minute that the finish line actually exists and that you're going to reach it. If you begin to let yourself doubt that the finish line exists and that you're going to reach it, you're afraid that by doubting that it exists, it will fail to exist, and then you'll have to admit that it's always been a big illusion, and that now you've got mud on your face, not glory. Finally, this ultimately happens, but it's quite possible that by the time it does happen, your self-esteem will have been eroded to such immeasurable degrees that you hardly recognize yourself in the mirror, and don't care at all what you look like to others, so long as they provide some kind of assistance in reinforcing your delusions. It is to them that you are both attracted and repulsed simultaneously; you are compelled to "fellowship" with them by divine imperative, though you wouldn't care to be around any one of them if you gained the courage to liberate yourself from your own self-deceit and left all of the hokum behind. Your fellowship is thus not motivated by genuine love for the individuals, for the values they represent and which you admire, but out of fear, fear of enacting your genuine desire: to become independent of them, and to have them independent of you, in essence, to deal with one another as political equals. Instead, it is obedience to a ruler that keeps you in check.

If that is the life you seek, if that is the life you want to live, Christianity can pack it in like no other.

Well, I've responded to every one of your points, and I think I've given you lots to think about. Please note that I am considering to polish up our correspondence to post it up on my website for public viewing. Particularly my first response to you, which addresses many of the particulars of the resurrection story. If you do not want your name published, please let me know. Otherwise, I will interpret our continued correspondence as your sanction to keep your name attached as is.

Face it, Mr. ____. You have not proven the outstanding claim that Jesus rose from the dead. No apologist has. Only through the subterfuge of a mind-game and reliance on fallacy can you construe any argument as supplying the necessary proof of Jesus' resurrection. What's more, while challenging me to disprove the resurrection, you not only fail to prove it yourself, but fail to meet the counter-challenges I offered by return. And finally, your apologetic is utterly impotent when it comes to attacking the foundation of my view of reality, to which I appeal in my rejection of all claims to the miraculous and magical. If you don't accept my position as sound, that is your choice. But if you want to continue repeating the futility of your position in future correspondence, all I can say is:

Never mind.

Besides, as you yourself state at the beginning of your last note, you must be amply busy with your schoolwork and household chores.

If, however, you sincerely want to explore some of my ideas or the ideas raised in some of the sources I cited in my responses to you, I welcome your questions and comments.

Otherwise, I will consider this a settled issue.

 

Anton Thorn

________________________________________

© Copyright by Anton Thorn 2001. All rights reserved.

 

[Back to Top]

[Back to Anton Thorn's Main Page]

[Back to Problems With Christianity]

[E-mail Anton Thorn: tindrbox@aol.com]