THE THEORY OF THE COMMON LAW BY JAMES M. WALKER CHARLESTON, S. C. BOSTON: LITTLE,BROWN AND COMPANY 1852 CONTENTS Page Introduction ................................................ 3 Chapter I The State .................................. 9 II Civil Person ............................... 11 III Remainders ................................. 13 IV Fee ........................................ 15 V Scintilla Juris ............................ 18 VI Contingent Remainders ...................... 19 VII Conditions ................................. 22 VIII Relations .................................. 23 IX Heir - The Rule in Shelley's Case .......... 25 X Warranty ................................... 29 XI Diversity of Rights ........................ 31 XII Joint Tenancy .............................. 34 XIII Jus Accrescendi ............................ 35 XIV Usufructs .................................. 36 XV Executory Interests ........................ 37 XVI Political Status ........................... 41 XVII Judicial Office ............................ 43 XVIII Courts ..................................... 44 XIX Citizenship ................................ 45 XX Aliens ..................................... 46 XXI Guardianship ............................... 49 XXII Courtesy ................................... 49 XXIII Dower ...................................... 52 XXIV Dower at Common Law ........................ 53 XXV Marriage ................................... 55 XXVI Conveyances ................................ 57 XXVII Possession ................................. 58 XXVIII Retrospect ................................. 62 XXIX The Tendency of the American Law ........... 63 XXX Conclusion ................................. 67 INTRODUCTION PART 1 The science of law, in its most comprehensive sense, is the body of rules of human conduct which are universally recognized as obligatory. In a more limited view, is the body of rules which constitute the code of a particular state. But in either sense, the basis of every system must be truth. The universal is true, because is consistent with the nature of man; the municipal is true, because it is consistent with the nature of the people subject to it. The truth of the municipal is not, however, the antagonist of the truth of the universal. For a law of a particular state may also be a law of humanity, or it may , as the law of aliens, be the law of every nation, without being the law of nature. The municipal differs from the universal only as a particular differs from a general truth. A body of law implies necessarily internal concordance or harmony of its rules. This agreement renders the mulitiude of special rules a law, a unity. They are together one law; thus we say, the law of England, the law of nations, the law of nature. A law signifies the relation of man to man; a body of laws, the relation of nation to nation; the universal law, the relation of man to God. When a law has been adopted by a people from the universal, than that law, the relation of man to man, is the true relation between man and man in the municipal and universal, is a special and general truth. That which is the true relation between man and man is the just relation, or justice, absolute as to the universal, relative as to the municipal. So, also, a law expresses not only the relation of man to man, but at the same time his relation to the supreme power. In like manner, a body of laws to the law of every other nation and to the supreme power the relation of the true and just; else those living according to that law will be enemies of mankind and the supreme power that governs them. As the law of each nation differs in important respects from that of every other, each unit is different in its nature, its tendency, and its mode of expression. Now, to constitute a unit of a multitude of rules, there must be some one idea which has affinity to every rule, and around which all may harmoniously be grouped. That idea will control the law in every part, and in all its modes of expression. It will determine the tendency of each system, and stamp upon is its own peculiar characteristics. That idea is the life of the law, and animates every member of the body politic. It begins with the birth, lives in the history, and dies in the last scene of the national drama. It must be found in every relation of man to man and society. The men of high and men of low degree, each family and each child, all property, history, and literature, must bear its indelible impression. That idea is, in short, the eminent truth of that people; and exposition of it in its application to law is the philosophy of law. The philosophical element of the law must be equally applicable to the public and private law of a state; else there would not be the law, but the laws, of England. In other words, one people would be subject to two coequal and discordant systems. The truth being than the same in both branches, the public and the private, its discovery in one is conclusive of its existence on the other branch. Our inquiry leads us to consider whether there exists in the Common Law an ides with the consequences which we have specified. How does that idea express itself in that system? What are its effects upon the people, its influence upon other systems, its power in directing the movements of the mind of humanity. These questions are within the province of the philosophical statesman. Our task is the humble one of establishing the existence of such an idea in the Common Law and exhibiting its control over the rules of property peculiar to that system. An indispensable instrument in the investigation of all scientific truth is method. Science cannot exist without it. Now our juridical writers altogether neglect it. For although the law is a collection of principles, they treat of it, not in reference to principles, the abstract, but in reference to things, the concrete. They neither descend from general to particular, the ordinary mode of imparting scientific information, nor ascend from particulars to generals, the ordinary method of discovering truth. This is the more remarkable, inasmuch as the science of the law has been not ineptly termed one of the exact sciences. The geometric or demonstrative method has been applied with remarkable success to the solution of questions of law. And that it deserves to rank as a science almost in the same class with geometry can easily be made apparent. Its terms are free from ambiguity, its first principles simple and obvious, the subjects with which it is conversant are wholly independent of things in actual visible existence, and are capable of being accurately defined. Their properties and relations are immutable. In these respects of sciences have the same qualities. Our surprise is not lessened by the consideration, that, whilst other moral sciences have been discussed in every variety of method, it should have been altogether neglected in a science which of all others is the most intimately acquainted with human relations, by which man lives, moves, and has his being in society, which makes his home a temple and a fortress, that no impious hand can touch with impunity, no daring adversary assail with success. But its neglect is a fact now, and when Bacon pronounced this judgment upon his age:"Qui de legibus scripserunt omnes, vel tanquam philosophi, vel tanquam jurisconsulti argumentum illud tractaverunt. Atque philosphi proponunt multa dictu pulchra, sed ab usu remota. Jurisconsulti autem .....placetis obonxii et eddicti.....tanquanm e vineulis scrmoeinantur." It is in this respect that the Roman has so great advantage over the Common Law. The universal error of our juridical writers is in supposing that, even in those countries over which the Civil Law presides, it is valued chiefly for its doctrines. The reverse is the truth. "When," says Professor Mayer, on the subject of the use of Civil Law in Germany, "its provisions shall have ceased to have the force of law, its study will produce greater profit, and the peculiar method employed by the so-called jurists in treating the law will be better estimated and turned to practical account." Again he says, "It ought ever to be remembered, that, familiar as they (the Roman lawyers) were with all the culture of their times, they knew the law not as an aggregate of rules, but in its scientific unity, such as it was disclosed to them by its own history and the history of their nation. The legal literature of no other people can show a casuistry so thoroughly spiritual, where the matter of fact only seem designed to corporealize and exhibit the spirit. Hence, there is no better training of practitioners PART II Jurisprudence is the knowledge of laws, their reasons, and their sources. Knowledge of laws and their sources constitutes the history of the law. Knowledge of laws and their reasons constitutes he philosophy of law. Without some tincture of this philosophy none can be said to understand the law; "for though a man can tell the law, yet, if he know not the reason thereof, he shall soon forget his superficial knowledge." To discern these reasons, it is indispensable to study the history of the law. The latter furnishes forth the facts, and in them philosophy searches for their reasons. Philosophy does not create, is discovers the true relations of things. The relation of man to man is expressed in the youth of nations in customs or usages, which embody the national ideas of justice, and in that way express the character of the people. For no custom can prevail in a nation which is repugnant to its sentiments of sense of justice. Manners are the law of a people at this stage of its progress. These are, then, parcel of the national mind; its moral rule, as well as the arbiter of public and private right. Morally they are the people. The athenians uttered a universal truth, when, abandoning their territory to its invaders, they said that their country was their customs, and these they carried with them in their ships. Nations in all ages have sent forth colonies which voluntarily separated themselves from their places of nativity, but never from their customs. In fact, they cannot; it is a moral impossibility. They cannot separate themselves from themselves. Hence colonies have always transported their native customs to their foreign homes, and have preserved them so far as they could, consistent with the altered relations of external affairs. In regard to the Germans of the medieval ages, this is equally true. An erroneous inference from this general truth has, however, been made. Their conquest gave them large territories, which were partitioned between themselves and the conquered people. Each man thus became a landlord. But this was altogether a new relation for them, and to which their customs had no reference; for before they crossed the Rhine, private property in land was absolutely and totally unknown to them. Their customs concerned their rights as men, life, liberty, and property in chattels; and even of these they possessed little more than their wagons, cattle and arms. Until they had conquered the Roman world, they knew nothing of conveyances, much less of devises of lands, a refinement upon the right of alienation. Nullum testamentum, says Tacitus, their customs were unwritten, leges memoria sola et usu tenebant. After their conquest, they became subject voluntarily to the influence of the laws, and gave a ready obedience to the Christian pontificate of Rome. Their national characteristics disappeared, in a great measure, in a new civilization; their customs were written, and in the language, and discolored with the ideas, of the conquered. So difficult is it to distinguish even in the Salic and Riparian codes the native form the Roman element, that this task is still admitted by eminent German scholars to be as yet unaccomplished. The fact that the Germans before their invasion had no law of real property, is of great consequence in our judicial history. Savigny has demonstrated that the codes of all the tribes consisted, in a great measure, of Roman law, and it has always been admitted that these were interpreted with the aid of that law. Hence the universal prevalence on the Continent of the Civil Law. The Norman customs, however, did not undergo so great modification. For, being the last of the invading tribes, bringing with them their native customs fresh and pure, they could not at once become Gallo-Romans. Nor, indeed, have they yet become so thoroughly imbued with the principles of the Civil Law as the Franks and Burgundians. The Anglo-Normans, insulated, and almost from the time of the conquest of England hostile to the Gallo-Romans, have the course been less deeply impressed with the mixed law of the Continent. But as the Normans had originally no native custom concerning land, they too, necessarily, when they became proprietors, adopted the only law of real estate of which they had any knowledge, the mixed Gallo-Roman law. The change from oral and traditionary to written laws is the beginning of legislation. Legislation is not the law, but the expression of the law antecedently existing. The thought was already in the mind and heart of the people. This is a truth in the juridical history of the world. Legislation cannot be other than the authoritative utterance of the thought of a people. The cause of this change from tradition to legislation has always been political. Thus the Twelve Tables were compiled to remedy the diversity between races, the Patrician and Plebeian. "The state of affairs," says Niebuhr, (Rome, Vol. II p.210) "was exactly like that which led to the framing of the statutes of modern Italy. When the German conquerors and the Romans had grown up together into one nation, with a common language and manners, the universal tendency of circumstances was to mould the two classes into civil communities with new rights, in which those previously separate should be blended." Hence these mixed codes of Roman law and national customs. A similar condition of affairs led Alfred and Edward the Confessor to promulgate their codes. These historical instances prove that the change from tradition to legislation was produced, not only by a political, but by the same political cause. And each of these codes, except that of Edward, became, for the people subject to it, fons omnis publici, privatique juris. The diversity of races, which the laws of Edward were intended to obliterate, arose in a new form after the conquest. William consented that the natives should be governed wy their own laws; but at the same time published his code for the government of his followers. This state of affairs tended necessarily to perpetuate the diversity, by establishing two coordinate systems of laws; but he gave the administration of both to the Normans. Interest, contempt for a conquered race, ignorance of the native laws, and a knowledge of their own, combined to render the judges utterly regardless of the native laws. A long period elapsed before the races had blended; but the traces of the Anglo-Saxon upon the law were few and slight. Their customs perished with the people who cherished them, as congenial to their manners and constant memorials of their lost freedom. And whilst the native was becoming obsolete, a foreign code was being substituted by judicial legislation. The next step in the juridical history of modern times is the promulgation of capitularies of statutes made by the sovereign alone. None of these are now referred to in England as authority, except Magna Charta of Henry the Third (A.D. 1225), two hundred years after the conquest. The antecedent capitularies are generally declaratory, and where remedial or amending, they have been directed to the correction of abuses in the administration of the jus corona. It is apprehended that they have had little influence in the formation of the Common Law. Although Bracton lived in the reign of Henry the Third, and wrote within a few years after Magna Charta was granted, he mentions it only passingly, and without attaching to it much importance. Indeed, until the Revolution, when Somers and his coadjutors sought justification of their ideas of popular rights in the law, Megna Charta was almost forgotten. And historically it is not true that the celebrated twenty-ninth chapter had for its purpose the extension of the power of the democratic element in the government. It was intended solely to confirm the owners of lands, liber homo, in the enjoyment of such rights as they had beforetime possessed. This statute, says Coke, was but a restitution of the Common Law, and his remark concurs with the truth of history. The English Revolution did, however, extend the basis of political organization, and increase the influence of the popular element. But it seems natural to the lawyer to discern in the past the exact prototype of the present, and it is certainly common to deny that the improvement of the law, public and private, is a change of the antecedent law. Development is with many not progress, and such desire the law to be immutable. The English Revolution made no change in the law of private property. In like manner, the American Revolution affected only the public law. The tenacity with which every branch of the great Germanic race maintains its primitive customs has always been remarked. The Normans and their descendants have adhered faithfully to their customs in relation to lands, which they adopted in the Middle Ages. Their law of real estate is altogether customary. No code nor statute establishes our system of real estate. Yet in the lapse of nine hundred years, diversified by every incident that can befall a people in prosperous or adverse fortune, advancing from comparative barbarism to the hight of civilization, chang dynasties, pendulating from the tyranny of the Tudors to the anarchy of the Barebones Parliament, indoctissimum genus indoctissimirun hominum, not one principle of the law of real estate has been altered. The Justinian of the English law restored the customary law by the statute de donis, and the tyrannical Henry the Eighth attempted to lop off that foreign graft in the Common Law, uses. Legislation, with few exceptions, has been confined to the accidental, and has not touched the essentials of the Common Law. Thus, the statute of frauds merely establishes the kind of evidence necessary to prove contracts in certain cases. The statute of wills extends the special customary law to the whole realm. The Habeas Corpus act gave another remedy for illegal imprisonment. Nor has legislation altered in a single particular conveyances at Common Law, but has increased indirectly their number. So the family relations remain, with their incidents, as they were in the earliest periods. This review shows that the Common Law presents for our investigation a continuity of doctrine, which binds the present to the past, a chain of rules unbroken by revolutions, and blurred by codification, in short, a body of original facts. Without the immutability of the Jewish law, it has been stable, amidst the changes of society. It has participated in great revolutions, without being a passing incident in the life of the nation. It is not an episode in the life, it is the life itself of the nation. It is stable, because its principles are founded upon truth; it is capable of amelioration, because that is of the nature of humanity. It must, then, have a philosophy. THE THEORY OF THE COMMON LAW CHAPTER I THE STATE The State is a person, and possesses as its property one territory. As this one civil person consists of all the citizens, so its property consists of all the individual property of the citizens. It is una persona, unicum patrimonium. This unity of person and property of the state is expressed by the Common Law in the maxim, that all lands were originally granted out by the sovereign, and are therefore holden, either mediately or immediately, in fee. The sovereign reserved the dominium and ultimate property in the lands, and the grantee acquired only the use and profits. Thus the right to the soil was separated from the right to the use and profits. In apprehension of law, the state holds the soil of the whole territory as one estate. This idea was not peculiar to the feudal law. It prevailed universally on the Continent, among the German tribes who conquered the Gallo-Roman provinces. Caesar states, that before their irruption into Gaul they had no private estates in land; "neque quisquam agri modum certum, aut fines proprios." The territory occupied by them belonged to the tribe, and was repartitioned annually to prevent even local attachments. In like manner Rome held the sovereignty over her conquered provinces. The possessors or tenants, whether Roman citizens or subjects, held their lands in bonis, as usufructs, and without that participation in political tights which enabled the citizen to hold lands within the proper territory of the city, ex jure quiritium. The latter, known as one of the res mancipi, corresponded to the legal estate of the Common Law, and was in the same sense distinguished from the usufruct. Thus Cicero applies the distinction, "ergo fructus est tuus, mancipium illius." Lueretius more eloquently and accurately says: " Vita mancipio nulli datur, oinnibus usui." This idea of the unity of the territory, being common both to the Germans and Romans, was adopted as the basis of the treaties between them previous to the fifth century. Thus, in A.D. 268, the Franks received lands upon the banks of the Rhine, on condition of defending that frontier from barbarian invasion and of serving as auxiliaries in the Roman army. Military service was the only rent that, from their previous migratory and predatory habits, they were capable of paying for the use of the lands. On the eastern frontier the same course was adopted; indeed, the Empire, assailed at every point by barbarous tribes, was compelled to employ some of them in its defence. Such also was the tenure of the Salic territory in the early period of the Middle Ages, and for that reason transmissible only to male heirs. Therefore, whilst those tribes in amity with Rome had the use and profits of their lands, the sovereignty termed dominium populi Romani by Gaius and imperium by Justinian - indicative of the different forms of government - belonged to the civitas or state. It would not be difficult to collect from history numerous other instances of the prevalence of this idea. Indeed, so generally has it been adopted as the foundation of political and territorial organization, that it is one of the points of similarity between the general outlines of theology and jurisprudence. Hence, too, the jurisconsult of antiquity - theologians, jurists, and philosophers at once - comprehended under the word Justice all the relations of man to man and to God. And therefore they defined jurisprudence to the divinarum atque humanarum rerum notitia, justi atque injusti scientia. This idea being the basis of the political and territorial organization of the whole state, its effects must necessarily be discoverable, in a greater or less degree, in every part of the legal system of the state. It is not possible that any people should live under a public law which is antagonistical to the private law. The reasons are too palpable to require any elucidation. Therefore, in treating of the private law, altogether to discard consideration of the public, is to neglect that element by which the private law exists. For instance, trial by jury in private causes we value highly; but no one could imagine that it would be valuable in a despotism. The form might survive, but not the life, and it would probably be merely an instrument of oppression. We shall, however, no further notice the public law than is absolutely necessary for the exposition of the private. It will be found that in proportion as the state tends towards unity or centralization, as it is now generally termed, so are the people free or not; and in the same proportion is the security of their rights of property. In the Common Law, as will hereafter be shown, the idea of the unity of person and of property is applied practically, and with controlling power, to every relation that can arise between the grantor and the grantee of lands, considered either as persons alone, or as persons in connection with property. Whatever may be the quantity or quality of an estate, into what number soever of parts it may be divided, however numerous may be the tenants, their relations depend upon this principle. They exist, as Bracton says, per juris unitatem. This unity is termed by Blackstone "a fiction of tenure," but, like all other legal facts, it will be found potential in the law, rigorous, and peremptory, admitting no contradiction and suffering no modification. It is the foundation, not only of the public political and territorial law, but of private property, of status, of family rights, of courts and their rules of procedure; in short, an exposition of it, as applied to the law of England, is the philosophy of the Common Law. CHAPTER II CIVIL PERSON The state is represented in the person of its chief magistrate, who is at the same time a member of it. Thus the king or president possesses two kinds of rights, a university of rights as a corporation, and individual rights as a man. As the former become more and more confounded with the latter, so government advances towards some form of monarchy. A bishop also is a sole corporation, but the man holding the office has also his individual rights. The word person neither according to its accurate meaning nor in law is identical with man. A man may possess at the same time different classes of rights. On the other hand, two or more men may form only one legal person, and have one estate, as partners or corporators. Upon this difference of rights between the person and the man, the individual and the partner, corporator, tenant in common, and joint tenant, depends the whole law of these several classes. The same person has perfect Power of alienation, of forming contracts, of disposing by last will and testament of his individual estate, but not of the corporate, nor of his own share in it, unless such power be expressed or implied in the contract by which the university of rights and duties is created. The same distinction divides all public from private property, and distinguishes the cases in which the corporation or civil person may sue from those in which the individual alone can be the party; although there are instances in which the injury complained of may, in reference to the difference of character, be such as to authorize the suit to be instituted either by the civil person or the individual, or by both. Thus, violence to the person may be punished either as a wrong to the state or to the individual. The true meaning of the word person is also exemplified in the matter of contracts. It is said, generally, that all persons may contract; but that is not true in the sense that all human beings may contract. Thus, a married woman, an infant, a lunatic, cannot contract. Again, a slave of mature age, sound intellect, with the consent of his master, cannot make a contract binding on himself, although as an agent he may bind his master. These matters are important only as they serve clearly to show that the civil person may have rights distinct from those which he possesses as an individual; and that his rights or duties as an individual may consequently become opposed to his rights and duties as a civil person. Thus, a partnership of three persons may own, for example, a moiety of a ship, and one of them the other moiety. In case of a difference between them as to its use, the rights of the one as a partner, and his right as an individual owner of another moiety, are directly opposed. In order, therefore, in any case, to perceive the application of a rule of law, it must be considered whether the person or the individual, or both, in the possessor of the right. For it may be asserted as absolutely true, that the rights of the man are not recognized by that law which is termed the municipal. It recognized them only as they grow out of, or are consistent with, his character as a civil person. In other words, this is the distinction between the Common Law and the law of nature. Nor is this a fanciful distinction, inasmuch as the rudest tribes, as well as the most civilized nations, have always distinguished between the rights and duties of their members, and of those who were not members of the body politic. Even after the philosophical jurists of antiquity had polished and improved the jurisprudence of aristocratic republican Rome by the philosophy of the Portico, Cicero, statesman, philosopher, and jurisconsult, exclaims with indignation against the confusion of rights of person that the age witnessed: "in urbem nostrum est infusa peregrinitas; nune vero etiam braccatis et transalpinis nationibus ut nullum veteris leporis vestigium appareat." The Common Law, as well as the Civil, recognizes as a person an unborn child, when is concerns its interests either as to life or property. "Qui in utero est perinde ac si in rebus humanis esset, custoditur, quotiens de commodis ipsius partus quaeritur." And both systems provide the same remedies to protect the child and those with whom its birth may interfere. In case of a limitation of the child to which a woman is now pregnant, if twins should be born, the Common Law gives the estate to the first-born; by our law, they would take moieties. Now, as these rights are acquired be for the birth of the child or children, there is a double fiction; not only in considering the unborn as born, but in distinguishing under the Common Law the eldest from the youngest born. Whilst, therefore, the law regards the unborn as born, yet to transmit the estate, he must be born as a man, alive and capable of living. The law does not presume the life of death of an individual; when his existence has been established, his death also must be proved. But the birth of an individual and the commencement of his character as a person do not necessarily concur. Thus, an alien of any age is not a person, in relation to a contract concerning lands, nor in any case is an infant; so a woman marrying before she attains her legal maturity may die of old age without having become a person, On the other hand, a person may suffer civil death before physical death; totally, where he becomes a monk; partially, as a penalty for the commission of an infamous crime; and perpetually of temporarily, as in case of outlawry. CHAPTER III REMAINDERS The unity of estates is exhibited in its simplest form in the fee simple. But in order that its influence in the more subtitle portions of the law may be made apparent, the doctrine of vested remainders will be considered. "it is a general rule," says Mr. Fearne, "that every reminder must vest, either during the particular estate, or else at the very moment of its determination. So that, if a lease be made to A for life, and after the death of A, and one day after, the land shall remain to B, this remainder of B is void." Why does the law inexorably demand that the remainders shall vest at the very instant of the determination of the preceding estate? Mr. Fearne states that "this rule was founded upon feudal principles, and was intended to avoid the inconveniences which might arise by admitting an interval when there should be no tenant of the freehold to do the services of the land, or answer to the stranger's praecipe, as well as to preserve an uninterrupted connection between the particular estate and the remainder, which, in the consideration of the law, are but several parts of the whole estate." The feudal principles to which Mr. Fearne refers seem to be those intended to prevent the inconveniences to the lord and the stranger, which would follow from the want of a tenant of the freehold. The explanation might be sufficient, if every remainder necessarily consumed the whole estate remaining after the determination of the preceding estate. Were there no reverter, reversion, or escheat, then, perhaps, the lord might suffer inconvenience. Moreover, when there was no tenant of the freehold able to render service to the lord, an infant, for example, the lord might enter and enjoy the profits of the land. The infant was in wardship. If there was no legal tenant, the land reverted to the donor. And in either case, the stranger had a person holding in his own right or in autre droit, to answer to his praeeipe. Nor is the necessity of an uninterrupted connection between the particular estate and the remainder a sufficient explanation. It involves, in fact, a petitio principii. Why was it necessary that this connection should be uninterrupted, even for a moment? Upon what principle does the law declare that a remainder is void, if there be, as in the case above cited, the interval of a day between the particular estate and the remainder? It is manifest that the reason of the rule has no relation to the length of the interval, a moment is as destructive as a year. In the former case, a moment, the want of a tenant could not impose any inconvenience, either upon the lord or a stranger; yet it defeats the remainder as certainly as the interval of a year. The length of the interval was unimportant, and the inconvenience, therefore, was not the reason of the rule. We apprehend that the rule is founded upon reasons very different from those stated be Mr. Fearne. Without disturbing the learned dust that has encrusted the writings of those system-builders who have maintained that fees were originally held at the will of the lord, and rose by degrees, passing through the stages of leases for years and for life, to the dignity of inheritances, it is sufficient for our purposes to fix ourselves upon that point of time when all agree that estates for life had become general. The tenant for life was bound to render to the lord certain customary services, and others that might be specially agreed upon between them. On his part, the lord was bound to protect the tenant in the enjoyment of the land, and, in case he was expelled by paramount title, to provide him with another feud. And, as connection between the lord and the vassal was personal, the latter could not substitute a vassal in his own place, nor the former a lord, without mutual consent. At the termination of the life estate and land reverted to the lord, again to be granted as a feud. It is probable that various motives conspired to induce the lord to grant the land to two or more persons, in secession, for life. Let us suppose the case of a limitation to A for life, and from and after his death to B for life. By the common law, livery of seizin was necessary to give title to a freehold interest in land. When, therefore, the tenant for life took livery of seizin, the remainder-man acquired an inchoate right to the remainder. This right vested in the remainder-man as soon as the particular estate commenced, but it did not authorize him to enter into the possession of the land, even at the death of the tenant for life, without the consent of the lord. "Sciendum est foeudum sine investitura, mullo modo constitui posse." Now, if the tenant for life forfeited his estate, and only by forfeiture could he lose it, it necessarily reverted to the lord: because the remainder-man, not having livery of seizin, could not enter, to exclude the lord, and livery could not be granted him, as remainder-man, under the original agreement, for the tenant for life was not dead. The resumption of the land by the lord was not the acquisition of a new estate, but his restoration to his original estate: for the tenure, or contract of holding, was that the lord might reenter for breach of any condition; being restored to his old estate, the remainder, necessarily, no longer existed. It ceased with the estate upon which is depended. The same principle is found in many other cases, and applied with even grater rigor. Thus, if a man seized of an estate in fee marries, and afterwards the condition is broken, and the lord enters for the breach, he will avoid the wife's title to dower. So, entry for breach, of condition will defeat all rent- charges, statutes, and judgments. To prevent, therefore, the failure of the remainder, consequent upon a reverter to the lord of his old estate, the tenancy for life must, in every case, continue until the moment when, by the law of the contract. the remainder man is entitled to demand livery of seizin. The rule, therefore, is grounded upon the plainest principles of justice. A remainder-man was in fact and in law, a party with the tenant for life in a contract with the lord. The tenant covenanted to perform certain obligations in praesenti; the remainder-man in futuro; and the lord contracted with both in praesenti. And it is clear that, by the contract, the rights of the remainder-man were dependent upon the fidelity of his coobligor, the tenant, to his obligations. This was the contract. It was a condition annexed to the contract, a part of the contract, that the life estate should be forfeited for certain causes. The contract, in the language of the civilians, contained a clause of nullity. We have seen, from Rolle and Coke, that even dower was avoided by a violation of the condition. So, by the Civil Law, if a mortgage was covenant of contract by which the estate was held was dissolved by the event of the condition, the mortgage would be defeated. This is in accordance with the general rule, Resoluto jure concedentis, resolvitur jus concessum. Thus, by both systems, the original proprietor resumed his estate, free from all encumbrances. As it is said by the common lawyers, he was in of his old estate. The remainder-man was therefore a party with the tenant in a joint contract with the lord. Being a joint contract, and not several and independent, the remainder necessarily commences as the time of the creation of the particular estate; or, in other words, a remainder cannot be created to commence in futuro. Hence, too, the interests of the tenant and remainder-man constitute but one estate in judgment of law. These are all the rules of the doctrine of vested remainders. CHAPTER IV FEE The principle of unity having been shown to exist with controlling power, not only over the whole territory, but every part of it, and also as entering as a substantive rule into the more complex portions of the law, its application is further to be considered. It is obvious that the maxim, that all lands are originally holden in fee, has two elements, jurisdiction and property, the dominion of the state or its sovereignty over the territory. "These, jurisdiction and property, are," says Grotius, "in reference to nations, usually acquired by one act." Now the distinctive peculiarity of the feudal law was to regard every lord as a sovereign, and every feud as a domain, and reversing what is in modern times considered the natural order of things, it attributed jurisdiction to the lord by virtue of his possession of land. M. Guizot marks this singular fact as the constituent element of that system, the fusion of sovereignty and property; that is, the attribution to the proprietor of the soil, over its inhabitants, of all those rights which constitute what we now call sovereignty, and which at this time are possessed only by the public. Again, Dr. Arnold says, the law of property, of real property especially, and a knowledge of all the circumstances of its tenure and divisions, would throw light upon more than the physical condition of a people; is would furnish the key to some of the main principles prevalent in their society. For instance, the feudal nation that property in land confers jurisdiction, and the derivation of property either from the owner's own sword, or from the gift of the stronger chief whose sword, has more deeply affected the political and social state of the modern nations of Europe. At Rome, as elsewhere among the free governments of the ancient world, property was derived form political rights, rather than political rights form property. And we may add, that this is true of the United States. This fusion of jurisdiction and property in lands was the peculiarity of the feudal system. The sovereign granted out the use and profits of the lands to his vassals, but regained sovereignty over them. By virtue of it, he imposed taxed, coined money, made war, sat as a judge in Aula Regis, surrounded with his vassals as a council. So, in like manner, every lord, upon receiving investiture of a fee from his superior, immediately acquired, by attribution of law, the rights of sovereignty over his vassals, and sat as a judge in his baronial court, surrounded by his vassals. Thus we read in Liber Feudorum: "Si inter suos vassalos de feudo sit controversia, domini sit congitio et per eum controversia terminetur." The greater barons made war, coined money, imposed taxes, and in short, exercised all the rights of a sovereign; the smaller were restrained, by their want of the necessary physical power, form asserting these rights in their plenitude. This was the only difference between the greatest and the least of the barons in the feudal age. The sovereignty exercised by a baron of any rank over his vassals was twofold; first, by means of his court, and secondly, directly and without its intervention. But in the course of time, as the turbulence of the state subsided, many instances of the latter class were enforced only by means of the court. For instance, the inquest at the suit of the crown to establish an escheat from want of heirs to the last person seized, has arisen since the feudal systems began to decline. The fact was always notorious, and the land was therefore immediately seized. An instance of this notoriety being sufficient, without further proof, will be found in the case of Dr. Storie, who was hanged for treason, being notoriously a native. The king, upon the commission of treason by rebellion, or denial of his feudal supremacy, did not, under the ancient Common Law, wait upon the pedetentous pace of the law, but instantly seized the lands of the traitor. The inferior lord, when his vassal denied his tenure, as by doing homage to another lord or attempting to alien his feud, also instantly entered and resumed his old estate. In both cases, of the king and the lord, the seizure was justified upon the same ground, that the tenant or vassal had denied his allegiance, and each exercised his right of entry. The right of entry is therefore a portion of the ancient jurisdiction or sovereignty of the owner of the fee. Furthermore, for the purpose of distinguishing clearly sovereignty or jurisdiction form property, we will analyze a fee simple. Littleton tells us, that a tenant in fee simple is he that hath the lands and tenements to him and his heirs for ever. But neither he, nor any other of our juridical writers, has given an account of a fee without any adjective, simple, conditional, tail, &c. It is not peculiar to lands, and may be of titles of honor, of offices, incorporeal hereditaments, and also of that species of personal property known as annuities. It is not the use and profits of land, nor necessarily annexed to them; for if lands be limited to A, and his heirs of his body, the fee continues in the donor, but the use and profits are the inheritance of A. It is not assignable not divisible, nor can we conceive of its partition into shares. Thus two tenants in common of an inheritance of one fee, but undivided moieties of the use and profits, but neither nor both can transfer the fee. When they transfer the use and profits with the consent of the lord, the law attributes to the donee the sovereignty or fee. Its existence is shown in the right of entry. As the king reserved sovereignty or jurisdiction, or, more properly, as it did not pass from him, so does the donor still continue to possess it, whenever he creates an estate of inheritance less than simple. Whenever the tenant violates his tenure, by treason or by alienation of his life estate in fee, the donor, whether king or tenant in fee simple, may exercise his jurisdiction and resume his estate. The manifest object of attributing to the lord this right of entry, or jurisdiction, was to enforce the faithful performance by the tenant of the duties incumbent upon him. As it is the power of punishing wrong, it is also necessarily the power of protecting right. Both these objects are combined in the office of trustees to preserve contingent remainders and uses. They have the right of entry upon the particular estate where the tenant attempts to destroy the contingent interests, and by their entry to preserve them. It is apparent, therefore, that the right of entry of fee is the last remnant of the jurisdiction that the feudal law attributed to property. Jurisdiction, fee, right of entry, is the ligament which binds the whole territory of the state and the several parts of it together in unity. That the word fee originally signified only the property in lands is certain; the jurisdiction exercised ny the lord was termed his sovereignty. Thus Coke terms the abbot of a monastery the sovereignty of the house. But, in the progress of time, the word sovereign came to be applied exclusively to the king, and jurisdiction ceased to be distinguished in language from the fee. Thus fee was made to comprehend jurisdiction, as well as the property. Thus confusion continues to the present time, and we use that word, in the present instance, for want of another familiar to us, and expressive to the attribute of property. CHAPTER V SCINTILLA JURIS Fee or sovereignty has no element of property, although by the feudal law it is the attribute of property. It exists only in legal apprehension, and is neither assignable, devisable, nor divisible. Now it is believed that the neglect to distinguish between the fee used in the sense of sovereignty, and fee as meaning property, has led both writers and judges into grave errors. For example, in Chudleigh's case, the limitation was to the use of A for life, remainder to his sons successively in tail. Before A had a son, the feoffees enfeoffed him in fee simple. The court held, that, by virtue of the statute of uses, all the seizin, estate, and possession of the feoffees were in the cestui que use in esse; and that a possibility of seizin continued in the trustees, to support the uses as they should arise. This is the much vexed question of the scintilla juris. Mr. Fearne has shown that this doctrine is irreconcilable with the statute of uses. But, with the utmost deference of the opinions of that eminent lawyer, it is believed, that, however complete may be his refutation of the doctrine of the court, his own explanation is equally untenable. Mr. Butler states it thus: "That by the statute the whole seizin is at once completely divested out of the feoffees, and that, when the contingent uses become vested, the use is executed in the person to whom it is limited, not in consequence of any seizin then accruing to the feoffees, but in consequence of the lands being originally conveyed to them with a liability in consequence of the statute to be attracted to the uses." The statute was intended to eradicate uses, but not to prevent the creation not to destroy contingent interests. Its purpose was to lop off from the law those foreign grafts, uses and trusts. The courts, to preserve these contingent estates, resorted to the scintilla juris. Mr. Fearne suggest "a liability to be attracted to the uses," annexed to the land. Now it is as difficult to comprehend this "liability" as the scintilla juris; and the latter phrase has this advantage, that it is used by Bracton, and the former has no authority for it. It is true, however, that Bracton uses it to express emphatically the entire absence of right, "nullum jus haberet nec juris scintillam ejieiendi." Moreover, Mr.Fearne reverses the rule of the law, that the land attracts the fee, and holds that the contingent uses attracts the land. But the statute changed the equitable into a legal estate; in did not and could not make the contingent a vested use; much less confer upon the contingent cestui que the enjoyment of the use and profits. Until they became vested, even considering them as merely legal, and not as equitable interests, the fee or jurisdiction continued in the feoffees, and was not assignable by them. That jurisdiction, fee, or right of entry was in itself sufficient to support the uses, without resort to the imaginary scintilla juris, which contradicted the statute or the liability, which has no authority for its use. The statute, then, has its full force, and the seizin estate and possession are transferred to the cestui que use in esse. When the other uses arise, they are supported by the right of entry. The feoffment by the feoffees was therefore a nugatory act. Nothing continued in them but jurisdiction or right of entry, which is not assignable. Nor can the right of entry be barred by a feoffment, for a Common Law anciently actual livery was necessary, and though subsequently, in the reign of Elizabeth, it was held that a feoffment by a mere wrongdoer in possession conveyed a fee, yet in the principal case the feoffees had not possession; it was in the eldest son A. If, therefore, it be admitted that trustees to preserve contingent uses may bar their right of entry, it is clear that a feoffment is not the appropriate instrument. That the court confounded sovereignty or fee with something of which seizin might be predicated, is palpable. Whereas, the feoffees had neither seizin estate nor possession, but merely a right of entry, that was not assignable, and which we cannot conceive as passing from them to the tenant. The liability which Mr. Fearne suggest as a convenient substitute for the scintilla juris, is equally incorrect. He fastens upon the land as a kind of lien what his opponents conceived to be a possession, or possibility of it. In fact, the court and himself mean the same thing, but they look at it on different sides; the court thought the feoffees had a possibility of right to the land, he thought that the lands were subject to a liability of duty. Neither, therefore, was correct; the feoffees had only a facultas, power, or right of entry, and they needed no more to support the contingent uses. It was not an interest, but just the identical right that the state has to seize the lands of a traitor, or that the donor and his heirs have to enter upon breach of a condition, or resume an estate after the death of the last special heir, to whom it has been limited. It is because the fee is jurisdiction, and not property, that a remainder cannot be created after a fee conditional. It cannot be divided, and therefore tenants in common and joint tenants have only one fee; although during their cotenancy they may enjoy the use and profits in different proportions. When their shares are divided and are taken in severalty, the law attributes to each its own fee or jurisdiction. CHAPTER VI CONTINGENT REMAINDERS It is requisite that the remainder be in the party to whom it is limited at the time of the livery. "This is regularly true; but yet it hath divers exceptions": these are contingent remainders. When it is said that the remainder must be in the grantee at the time of the livery, it is evident that nothing more is thereby meant, than that the right to the enjoyment of the use and profits after the death of the tenant then begins. In the mean time they belong to the tenant of the freehold. Now, where that right is limited to an uncertain person, the rule that the right must be in the party to whom it is limited as soon as the livery is made, cannot be observed. Hence some persons, to fulfil the letter of the rule that the remainder must pass out of the donor and be in the donee, insist that, so long as the person is uncertain, the fee is in abeyance. It would be sufficient to refer to Mr. Fearne for a refutation of his notion, but that his argument implies that fee has some element of property. Stating the proposition correctly, that nothing remains to the donor, after he has disposed of the use and profits, but jurisdiction, there can be no pretence for the doctrine of abeyance. When a lord or tenant in fee simple has created a freehold interest, with a contingent remainder over, he has divested himself in favor of the tenant of the use and profits, and has nothing more than jurisdiction and the ultimate property. His fee can no more be in abeyance than that of the state would be if it created a similar estate. The donor has the right of entry to protect the contingent interest, or, if he has created none, to protect his reversion or reverter. It can be used only against the tenant, and not against the remainder-man, whether vested or contingent. It is for the benefit of the latter, and hence its mere existence is sufficient to support these limitations. From the fact that it is the duty of the trustees to exercise the right of entry to preserve contingent remainders, springs their liability to punishment for its abuse, or non-user. The duty which the trustees owe to the contingent remainder-man, although an uncertain person, gives that person, when known, a right; so that, in fact, there is between the trustees and the remainder-man a contract. That the uncertainty as to the person who may have the right to enforce a contract does not negative its existence, is shown in many cases. Thus, where a person binds himself by his obligation to pay another, his heirs, executors, or administrators, L100, upon the death of the obligee, he may or may not have executors; and either way, before his death, it is uncertain upon whom will devolve the right to enforce the contract. When the suit is instituted, it is not as upon a new right accruing subsequent to the death of the obligee, but upon the original contract. In case of a limitation to the heirs of B, it is certain that, at his death, he will have heirs. These would, therefore, by the terms of the limitation, take the estate, although the heirs of B should not be in existence at the death of B, as if he survived the first taker. There is nothing in the contract, or words of limitation, to negative this view. But it is certain that the heirs of B will not take the estate unless he dies before the tenant, and during the continuance of the particular estate. The remainder takes effect, provided that the condition upon which it is limited is performed during the life estate. This rule, which inexorably demands that the remainder should vest, a latest, eo instanti with the death of the first taker, is the public law, and no part of the contract between the donor and donee. The former cannot vary it or introduce any modifications of it. The public law requires that its fundamental principle, the unity of estates, should be observed. But we allude to this subject at this time more particularly to notice that the vested and contingent remainders differ in this respect, that the latter are dependent upon a condition. The uncertainty of the vesting of the contingent remainder is because that event, its vesting is suspended by a condition which may not happen or be performed during the continuance of the particular state. Mr. Fearne uses the phrase "event of condition," in his definition of a contingent remainder, and in all his rules except the third, event. But it is evident that the definition is properly a summing up of his rules. Moreover, it will be seen, upon examination, that his four classes can, without prejudice to their accuracy, be stated in another form of words, which will admit the use of one or other of the four phrases which, according to Code, are peculiarly expressive to conditions. This is noticeable only because it lays open the true elements of the doctrine of contingent remainders. The law of these limitations is the doctrine of conditions. controlled by the principle of the unity of estates. Thus, an estate may be limited to A for life, and form and ten years after his death to the heirs of Be, without conflict with any rule of the doctrine of conditions; but such a limitation would be void, because it would sever the unity of the estate. These exceptions, contingent remainders, are admitted into the law, therefore, upon intelligible principles. The feudal principle which still inhabits our law requires that the interests of the tenant and remainder-man should be united. It would defeat the jurisdiction of the donor, if, when the tenant forfeited, the remainder-man, whom we have seen to be a joint contractor with the tenant, did not also lose his right; and this would follow if another interest, independent of the freehold, intervened between those two estates. But so long as the unity of the estate is preserved, the remainder may be made to depend upon any limitation, condition, proviso, that the donor may dictate. Cujus est dare, ejus est disponere. The condition annexed to the remainder only renders it uncertain during the previous estate. The tenant is certain at the time of the happening of the condition. Where the condition, however, not only renders the limitation over uncertain, but also the duration of the life estate itself, it is a conditional limitation, according to Mr. Fearne, and void a Common Law. CHAPTER VII CONDITIONS The doctrine of contingent remainders is, as we have seen, the application to remainders of the law of conditions, circumscribed as to the time of their performance by the public law. "conditio dicetur cum quid in casum incubum qui potest tendere aut esse aut non esse confertur." When coupled with an interest in property, as in case of a remainder, than the definition of the Civil Law is more accurate. "Conditio appellatur, enentus a cujus futura et incerta existentia, pendere obligationem aut ultimam voluntatem, contrahentibus testatori ve placuit." Pothier defines it thus: "A condition is a case of a future event which may or may not happen and upon which the obligation is made to depend." The rules of conditions are not exclusively confined to the law, but are equally applicable to every moral science. They constitute a part of logic, and when applied to legal propositions, of legal logic. A condition neither affirms not denies any proposition, but suspends it. It is the significant of doubt, rendering the proposition or limitation to which it is annexed uncertain. The conditions which concern contingent remainders, or other such interests, must be distinguished form those conditions usually termed implied, not only because the former are expressed, but because they differ materially in their natures. An implied condition may alter or defeat an estate, but never creates an estate. They seem rather to be essential parts of a contract, unexpressed terms of it, than accidents. Thus, no life estate or fee conditional can be created without an implied condition that the donor may enter for breach of it. Every ante-nuptial settlement implies that the conveyance shall be void in case the marriage does not happen. Moreover, these conditions do not suspend the limitations of estates to which they are annexed. The use of logic is, among other things, to determine the right use of terms, and thus to point out the abuse of them, and also to distinguish between terms rightly used, and the matures and properties of the different terms. The application of logic to legal questions has ben admirably illustrated by Mr. Fearne, in his treatise in Contingent Remainders. After defining such a limitation, and stating four classes of contingent remainders, he proceeds to show the true meaning of these words. In his third section, he distinguishes conditional limitations form contingent remainders, which Mr. Douglas had confounded, and in the remaining part of the chapter he shows that, by abuse of terms, vested have been mistaken for contingent remainders. In short, he shows by his criticism, that the words which were supposed to create conditions did not, and therefore that the remainders were vested. This discussion occupies the greater part of his treatise, and, as has been observed by Mr. Butler in his preface, "No work on any branch of science affords a more beautiful instance of analysis." Mr.Fearne continues his logical criticism, and shows that certain words seem to imply conditions, but that these are false conditions, not conditions. Thus, the definition of a condition requires that the condition should render the limitation uncertain, not impossible. Hence, if an event must happen, as death, the limitation is not uncertain, and therefore is unconditional; if it cannot happen then it is impossible, and the limitation is unconditional. In the former case, the limitation over is vested and valid, in the latter the limitation is void. Again, under the head of impossibilities, are conditions against law; it would be an absurdity to term that a legal condition, which can be performed only by an illegal, immoral, or indecent act. The definition also requires that the event of the condition should render the limitation certain or uncertain; that the event should cause the limitation to take effect, or to be defeated. therefore it cannot create or destroy a part of the limitation. It requires that the condition should produce certainty or uncertainty as to that limitation. Hence it must create or defeat that limitation, not another, and different one. A condition is the significant of doubt, and merely an accident annexed to the limitation; therefore, of the event is an infringement of the limitation, it is inconsistent with it and cannot be annexed to it, and therefore the condition is void; as that upon a certain event a fee simple shall not be alienable. These are some of the principal rules of logic, and have been noted with reference to the treatise on Contingent Remainders. In that work the examples and illustrations will readily be found. To attempt to epitomize it, would be to injustice, as it contains no matter superfluous to the practical lawyer or the legal specialist. Conditions are either precedent of subsequent. This division is founded upon a regard to the consequence of them, and not upon their location in the deed, nor upon their terms. They are precedent when they are the beginning, and subsequent when they are the ending, of a limitation. Yet a condition may be at the same time both precedent and subsequent, the beginning and the end. For instance, in the case of a conditional limitation, the same condition in reference to the previous estate is subsequent and its end, and in reference to the limitation over, it is precedent and its beginning. And that the limitation over is a conditional limitation is because of the uncertainty that the condition will be performed; if that was certain, then it would mark the natural termination of the particular estate, and the limitation over would be a remainder. CHAPTER VIII RELATION Ordinarily a contract upon condition specifies the time at or before which the condition must be performed; in the absence of such specification, the law fixes it. But in reference to contingent remainders the law does not leave it optional with the donor to specify the time, but demands inexorably that the condition be performed during the life of the tenant of the particular estate. At the moment of his death, the remainder must be capable of vesting in possession; although by the contract the condition may be required to be performed before that period. In like manner, the heir must be capable of taking at the time of his death, as if, being heir apparent, he becomes civiliter mortuus, the estate will not devolve upon him. Now, the tenant of a particular estate has one estate, and as to him the remainder-man has one estate. Yet both, by reason of the jurisdiction of the donor, have as to him one estate. The relations, however, of the tenant and remainder-man towards each other, are, as we have seen, determined by contract, but their relations to the donor depend upon jurisdiction. As to each other, the tenant has only the enjoyment of the use and profits before they pass or devolve upon the remainder-man. Such, too, is the relation of the ancestor and heir; setting aside the consequences of the jurisdiction of the ancestor, and having regard only to his enjoyment of the use and profits, and their devolution upon the heir. Both the heir and remainder-man obtain the use and profits at the death of the party who previously enjoyed them. The seizin of the tenant and that of the ancestor are the seizin of the heir and remainder-man; disseizin reduces them to a right of entry, and that being tolled to a right of action. It is to be observed, that the right of an heir does not begin with the death of the ancestor. For the seizin of the ancestor, not his possession, gives seizin to the heir, and seizin was obtained at the commencement of the estate. It is a rule of the Common Law, that no inheritance can vest in possession till the ancestor is previously dead. Before that time, the person who is next in the line of succession is called heir apparent of heir presumptive. Heirs apparent are such whose right of inheritance is indefeasible, provided they outlive the ancestor; heirs presumptive are such whose right of inheritance may be defeated. Nor is this rule of referring the right back to a time anterior to the death of the ancestor, limited to the case of heirs. Thus the remainder is referred back to the commencement of the particular estate. The donor of a fee conditional which has reverted to him by failure of issue, is in of his old right, not of a new estate. A wife's right to dower is referred back to the marriage, and will prevail against a subsequent charge imposed on the estate. Coke, after stating a case of a rent charge being displaced by the right of dower, remarks: "In which case two notable things are to be observed. First, albeit the dower be by relation or fiction of law above the rent, yet she shall not have her entire rent out of the residue, for a relation or fiction of law shall never work a wrong, or charge a third person; but in fictione juris, semper est equitas." These fictions, however much they may startle the minds of those undisciplined in the reason of the law, are legal truths, admitting no contradiction. Further illustration of this fiction will be found in conveyances by Common Law and by custom of copyhold. The surrenders of copyholds are construed as deeds and conveyances at Common Law. If a copyholder surrender to the use of his will, and devises to a stranger, and then dies, the devisee by his admittance takes as of the day of the surrender. So where at Common Law a person, having made a will of lands, acquires afterwards other lands, and dies, not having republished his will, the devisee takes as of the time of making the will, and therefore does not obtain the lands after acquired. So, says Lord Chief Baron Gilbert, in his book on Tenures, there is no rule better founded in law, reason, and convenience, than this, that all the several parts and ceremonies necessary to complete a conveyance shall be taken together as one act, and operate from the substantial parts by relation. Livery related to the feoffment, enrolment, to the bargain and sale, a recovery, to the deed which leads the uses; so admittance relates to the surrender. The retroactive effects of grants are seen also in the case of an alien, who has issue; that issue is not inheritable to his father, but if he be naturalized that issue may inherit. But if one be made denizen, the issue that he hath afterwards shall be heir to him, but no issue that he had before. Again, "There is a great diversity as to the forfeiture of land between an attainder of felony by outlawry upon appeal and upon an indictment; for in case of an appeal, the defendant shall forfeit no lands but shall as he had a the time of the outlawry pronounced; but in case of an indictment, such as he had at the time of the felony committed." So that, if he had given away his lands, in the latter case they would still be forfeitable. CHAPTER IX HEIR - THE RULE IN SHELLEY'S CASE Closely connected with the doctrine of remainders is the rule in Shelley's case. Where a limitation is made to A for life, remainder to the heirs or heirs of the body of B, A has only a life estate. But if the limitation be to A for life, remainder to the heirs or heirs of the body of A, he has an inheritance. The former is, and the latter in not, a remainder. The only reason given by out writers for this difference is, that the latter limitation is within the rule in Shelley's case. Mr.Fearne states thus: "Wherever an ancestor takes an estate of freehold, and a remainder is thereon limited mediately of immediately in the same conveyance to his heirs or to the heirs of his body, such remainder is executed in the ancestor." Why? Neither the grand argument of Mr. Justice Blackstone in Perrin and Blake, not the admirable criticism of Mr. Fearne on that case and the rule itself, enlightens us as to its origin. It is too important, however, not to receive careful consideration. An estate in fee did not originally pass an estate in the same sense as we now use it. For instance, where an estate was granted to a person and his heirs, he could not alienate it without the consent of the heir. The heir took by purchase, and not by descent. This was equally true of base or qualified and conditional fees. But before the time of the Glanville (A.D. 1189), tenants in fee simple, as we now term them, had acquired the power, but tenants in fee conditional still continued unable, to alienate. When Bracton wrote (A.D. 1268), the latter had also obtained the right of alienation. This, it is universally admitted, was produced by judicial legislation. To correct this novelty, and restore the ancient Common Law, the statute de donis enacted (A.D. 1285). It was merely declaratory, and enjoined that the will of the donor secundum formam chartae, which had beforetime been disregarded, should thereafter be observed. It is at this point that our law diverges from the English law. Fees tail with them correspond exactly to the fees conditional of the Common Law; at all events, if they do not, it is because courts have adopted principles irreconcilable with the statute de donis. In this country, fees conditional at Common Law are recognized, and at the same time the rule in Shelley's case. It is totally unnecessary to resort to the idea of the performance of a condition by the ancestor to execute the remainder in him, for the limitation is within the very letter and spirit of the rule in Shelley's case. And to apply this rule in the performance of a condition to fees conditional at Common Law is an error, inasmuch as juridical history and English legislation prove that where a limitation was made at Common Law to A and the heirs of the body, they took by purchase, and not by descent, and upon the death of the ancestor might recover the estate by a suit at law. However, juridical writers have stated that they are conditional fee for this reason, that it was a condition implied, that, if the ancestor begot heirs of his body, he should have an inheritance. As well might it be said, that, where an estate was granted to A and his heirs, it was upon condition that he should have an inheritance if he had heirs. For by the ancient Common Law, as we have seen, he could not alienate if he had heirs, and such, the stature de donis declares, was the Common Law of conditional fees. In these cases, the words heirs and heirs of the body only determined the quantity of estate that passed from the donor, and both cases upon the failure of heirs, general or special, the land reverted to the donor. This is the only conclusion that can be drawn form Bracton, who wrote (A.D. 1268) seventeen years before the enactment of the statute de donis. He is, therefore, the latest authority on this subject. After stating a coarcted limitation to particular heirs, he says, "Si autem, nullos tales haeredes habuerit, revertatur illa terra, ad donatorem per conditionem tacitam etim si mulla mentio in donatione habeatur." Which may be translated thus: "If the tenant shall have no heirs of his body, the land reverts to the donor by an implied condition, even of none be expressed in the deed." Again, he states that, as the remoter heirs are excluded, of the heirs of the body fail, the land reverts to the donor by a condition expressed or implied; "in quo casu,cum omnes haeredes remotiores excluduntur,sit terra revesura ad donatorem per conditionem tacitam vel expressam si tales haeredes dificeuint sicut adjieit donotor in eharta donationis." The condition was not to enlarge the estate of the tenant, but to cause it to revert to the donor. In other words, the condition was not that he should have a fee upon the firth of issue, but that if he did not have issue it should revert to the donor, and if he did have heirs it should go to them secundum formam chartae. Plowden states the rule with accuracy in the following sentence: "The fee simple absolute was where land was given to a man and his heirs; the other, to the heirs of his body, which was also fee simple." (Why, when, was the birth of issue not a condition in both cases?) "But in this case (fee conditional) there was a condition annexed to it, that, if he died without heirs, the land should revert to the donor." Clearly the condition was for the benefit of the donor, and whereby he might regain his old estate, and not for the benefit of the donee, and to enlarge his estate. We apprehend, therefore, that it was upon some other ground than the performance of a condition by the donee, that the fudges determined that upon the birth of issue the limitation to heirs of the body was executed in him. And the true ground is, as we have before intimated, the rule in Shelley's case. Blackstone attributes the interpretation of these limitations adopted by the judges to their sense of the inconveniences of fettered inheritances. The clamorous demand of the barons for the enactment of the statute de donis proves that they did not feel these inconveniences, and they owned nearly every acre in the kingdom. Many attempts were made in the succeeding two hundred years to repeal it, but it had contributed so much to the increase of the power of the barons, that they always refused their consent. At length, Taltarum's case was got up by Edward the Fourth, and estates tail were defeated by the astutia of the judges. An open avowal of the sentiment, that these estates were inconvenient to the crown, as they were insuperable impediments to the royal vengeance and rapacity, would have been extremely perilous to the reverend bench. They exhibited their astutia by applying to these limitations a rule derived from the Civil Law. The subject deserves examination, not only because of the importance of the rule in Shelley's case, but because is will uncover also the true character of the heir at Common Law, an inquiry which has been altogether neglected by our juridical writers. It is certain that, where a limitations was made to the heirs of the body, these were intended to take by purchase, and not by descent. Such was the old Common Law. "But if a man," says Lord Coke, "makes a gift in tail, or a lease of life, the remainder to his right heirs, this remainder is void, and he hath the revision in him; for the ancestor during his life beareth in his body in judgment of law all his heirs, and therefore it is truly said that haeres est pars antecessoris. And this appeareth in a common case, that if land be given to a man and his heirs, all his heirs are so totally in him as he may give the land to whom he will. Here, the idea expressed is, that during the life of the ancestor he and his heirs are one person, the heir is part of him. So the family and the father, in judgment of law, are one; their rights are his, and can only be vindicated, as to other persons, by and through him. So the rights of all the families in a state are so totally in the state that it may dispose of them. The idea of the unity of the father and son, the ancestor and heir, was familiar to the Romans. Cicero, in his philosophic treatise on laws, recognizes it: "Coronam virtute partam, et ei qui peperisset et ejus parenti, sine fraude lex impositam jubet." On the other hand, the heir quoadmodo during the life of the ancestor joined with him in the property. Thus Cicero, in his speech against Verres, says of children, "Quibus cum vivi bona nostra partimur." So Justinian: "Sedsui quidem haeredes ideo appellantur, quia domestici haeredes, et vivo quopue patre, quoadmodo domini existimantur." Again, in a play of Terence, a father speaking of his son calls him "meus particeps"; haeres pars antecessoris. The Code states it thus: "Cum et nature pater et filius, eadem esse persona pene intelligantur." Indeed, the word haeres, heir, is only another form of herus, owner. By the adoption of this rule of the Civil Law, that the heir and the ancestor are one, the limitations to the heir where executed in the ancestor. The heir did not, by the civil Law, acquire the right after the death of the ancestor; he then succeeded to him in the enjoyment of the use and profits. Upon the same principle, the earnings of the child became the property of the father. The latter absorbs all his rights, and his wrongs can only be vindicated by the father. Hence, in the language of Lord Coke, "if land be limited to a man and the heirs of his body, all his heirs are so totally in him as he may give the land to whom he will." The maxim that nemo est haeres virentis is strictly applicable to this explanation. Heir means, in that maxim, owner. Before the death of the ancestor, he is heir apparent; but in a particular case, as Coke shows, the heir apparent may also be complete heir and have the use and profits of an estate. He is termed the haeres astrarius, and he takes by descent; for if he took by purchase, he would be subject to relief. The peculiar character of heirship is discoverable in every part of the law, and will be still further developed in the next chapter. CHAPTER X WARRANTY Where a limitation was made to the heirs, or heirs of the body, we have seen that the estate in remainder became executed in the ancestor. Now, in case the ancestor sold the estate, ho was bound by the feudal law to protect the purchaser in its enjoyment, and in case of eviction, to recompense him with other lands. Thus was termed a warranty of covenant real, and bound the lands as a lien, into whose hands soever they passed by descent. And as feoffment, fine, exchange, partition, were the only species of conveyance, the feoffer was always bound by an implied warranty, in every sale of lands. Express warranties could scarcely exist, inasmuch as writing was to the generality an unknown art. Thus, by the ancient Common Law every sale of lands implied a warranty, and so far is identical with the Civil Law. Good faith is the foundation of warranty in both systems. When deeds came into use, the warranty was expressed. This would, of course, exclude any implied warranty inconsistent with the express; and in that sense it is true that expressio unius exclusio alterius. "For if A make a feoffment by dedi, and in the deed doth warrant against J. S. and his heirs, yet dedi is a general warranty during the life of the feoffer," so that the feoffee could vouch the feoffer during his life. "And of a man make a lease for life, reserving a rent, and add an express warranty, here the express warranty doth not take away the warranty in law, for he hath the election to vouch by force of either of them." In a previous passage, Coke states: "Note that by the Civil Law every man is bound to warrant the thing that he selleth or conveyeth, albeit there be no express warranty; but the Common Law bindeth him not, unless there be a warranty either in deed or in law, for careat emptor." Neither doth the Civil Law bind him to warrant, unless there be a warranty express or implied. It bindeth him to warrant every thing he selleth, for instance, land; so does every conveyance at Common Law. These are feoffment, fine, exchange, partition. But Coke has overlooked, in the above passage, the difference between conveyances at Common Law, and those having their operation under the statute of uses, a difference of which Mr. Fearne has made great use in his essay on Contingent Remainders. It is this, that conveyance under the state of uses transfer only the right of the donor, whilst those at Common Law convey the right of the party, destroy contingent estates, and invest the donee with an absolute fee. It is in the former that express warranty is indispensable, and to them that the rule caveat emptor properly applies. So caveat emptor applies, for the same reason, to sales by official persons, as sheriffs and masters in chancery, whose deeds are not properly conveyances, but memorials of the execution of judgments and decrees. It is plain, therefore, that the Civil does not differ from the Common Law, but from that law concerning conveyances which has grown up under the statute of uses. The rule of the Common Law is, that the heir is not bound unless named. The extent of his liability is determined by the value of the assets. It is important to distinguish between his liability and the extent of it. When his consent was necessary to alienation, no doubt he was named or joined. So, after deeds came into use, he was named or joined, and his liability was to make recompense in case of the eviction of the tenant. Now an heir cannot divest himself of that character, for he is born heir; and if, therefore, the rule that the heir, if named, was bound, was strictly enforced, his heirship would have been often highly detrimental. To correct this, a modification was introduced, which did not alter the nature of heirship, but limited his liability to the amounts of assets. The modification is sometimes expressed thus, that the heir is bound only as tenant of the lands. But it will be seen that the question therein was, substantially, whether the heir should have the benefit of the modification of the rule, and be held liable only to the extent of assets. His liability as heir was conceded. The like modification prevails in case the heir is named in a bond of the ancestor. Then the heir, as in the former case, is responsible as heir, but his liability does not extend beyond assets. In an action on the fond, he was sued in the debet and detinet, whilst an executor is sued only in the detinet. The latter was the representative of the deceased debtor, the heir was charged as the debtor. And he could not plead that there is an executor who has assets; he must confess the action and show the certainty of assets. For the obligation is a personal lien. Now the heir cannot be accounted the debtor in such case, where all the personalty goes to the executor, without admitting that he and the ancestor are one, independent of assets. And in all this, says Lord Chancellor Macclesfield, "the Common Law imitated the Civil Law." The Romans regarded heirship just as the Common Law does. Insolvency was with them a disgrace, not only to the unfortunate debtor, but to his family. It was a powerful objection, in vulgar apprehension, to the claims of a candidate for office, that his father was a bankrupt. To prevent this disgrace, the common practice was to appoint a slave the heir. Where he died intestate, the praetorian law intervened and permitted the heir to renounce his right as heir, and to take the estate, as a possessor bonorum, or tenant, or bailee, who then filed his inventory of the assets, by which both he and the creditors, unless they could show fraud, were bound. In fact, it was a plea of riens per descent, or only a limited amount of them. But the character of heir was unchanged. The Common Law did not pass through these modifications, but adopted the rule as it existed in the Civil Law of the later times. It may be added, that the characteristics of heirship enter also into the law of conditions. A warranty is a covenant of the benefit of the donee and his heirs, a condition generally for the benefit of the donor and his heirs. Neither of these can be assigned, at Common Law, to a third person, but both of them descend to heirs. No chose in action can be assigned to a third person. Is descent an assignment to a third person? No heir can take by purchase the interest that he might take by descent. Now the heir does take by descent, and that is not an assignment to a third person. The only explanation of this difficulty is, that the heir in apprehension of law is one with the ancestor, haeres pars antecessoris. Hence his land is attributed to the father, and rights are vindicated by the father, and upon the death of the latter, the heir is not a third person, but the same person, and therefore personally a debtor for the obligations of the father. The effect, therefore, of the rule in Shelley's case and warranty is to maintain the unity of person and estate. CHAPTER XI DIVERSITY OF RIGHTS The law recognized this division of rights; 1. Those which spring from the relation of parties to a particular purpose, as the rights springing from commerce by partners, and those rights which relate to a particular property, as of joint tenants. 2. Those rights which are not connected with any particular purpose or estate, the rights of an individual. Between the rights of a society, partnership, or joint tenancy, and those of an individual, not a partner, joint tenant, or corporator, there is a broad and plain difference. But when we consider that the same individual has rights as such, and also, at the same time, as a corporator, of partner, of joint tenant, or citizen, it is extremely difficult to define accurately what, in judgment of law are the rights of the associate and the rights of the individual. Thus, the difficulty is very grate in the case of rights to land in which the rights of the individual and of the corporator are intimately blended. It may be said, in general terms, that as a corporator of joint tenant his rights are such as the law of the corporation or joint tenancy recognizes. But the individual right springs from the general right, and is only distinguishable from it when the individual exercises it. So that this general proposition, however true in the abstract, does not aid us in obtaining a clear apprehension of the cases to which it is properly applicable. Now, the necessity of some rule by which we may distinguish these classes of right is very manifest, for thereby in practice we should arrive at correct conclusions, not only as to the rights, powers and duties of the corporator, but also of the individual. Such a rule, for example, would determine when a contract bound an individual as a partner, that is, was obligatory on the partnership, and when it did not bind that society, but bound the individual. It is plain that the question under consideration, therefore, touches the foundation of the most important affairs of corporations public and private, partnerships, and all other unions of men, with or without connection to property. Perhaps the nearest approximation that can be made to certainty in the mode of distinguishing these classes is by reference, not to the nature of the right, but to the exercise of the means of maintaining and preserving it. For instance, the state protects each individual in the enjoyment of his property, without denying to him the right of protecting it himself. But it does not interfere and use the means of protection, unless the invasion of property is accompanied with disturbance of the public peace. The state, before it interferes, regards the end for which it was formed. In like manner a corporation, the legal entity, does not become a party to a suit where the rights of one corporator are invaded by another; nor where one partner injures his copartner, does the partnership interfere; and, in both these cases, for the reason that the end of purpose for which the society was created does not demand it. But in all these cases, where the end or purpose does require it, the corporation, partnership, joint tenancy, or other association, does become a party. There are cases, however, in which the corporation or state may interfere, without denying, at the same time, the right of suit to the individual, as in case of an assault and battery. But still the ends intended to be accomplished by the state and by the person injured are different. The former vindicates the public peace, the latter, the wrongs done to his person. But it is clear that the suit has no reference to the nature of the right, for the individual may be, or he may not be, a member of the state. At the same time, it is to be admitted that the rule suggested does not meet every case that can be conceived. Thus, two persons own jointly White-acre and one of them owns Black-acre, the adjoining parcel of land, and a question arises as to the true boundaries; or suppose that a firm claims to be a creditor of one of its members; in such cases a regard to the end does not direct us to the proper means of determining that question. The same proposition was submitted to Pomponius, that eminent Roman lawyer, whose opinions have been adopted into the Digest. He answered, as we do, that, before the question could be determined by law, the society must be dissolved. The law has three distinct purposes: 1. To maintain the existence and well-being of society. This is true of every society, public of private, corporate of incorporate. 2. To maintain and preserve the person and property of each individual member free from all burdens which are not common to every other member. 3. To maintain and preserve the special rights of each member, and also of each member in relation to property. These special rights of person are, for example, the rights of magistrates, special rights of property, as casements. These manifestly are altogether accidental, varying in various societies and in the same society at various times, and always dependent upon the will of society. But the first and second class are fundamental principles, which cannot be varied in any material degree, without the destruction of the very purposes of society. We shall, therefore, omit all further notice of the third of these classes. The means of accomplishing the just end are sometimes general and sometimes individual; general, when a society defends itself or asserts its rights against non-members, or members; individual, when one member invokes the aid of the law against a fellow member. As to the second class, the means are individual; thus, and individual or class, upon whom a tax supposed to be unequal is imposed, or a larger share of contribution towards debts. But it is evident that in all such cases of the second class the party complaining must be a member. Hence an alien is excluded from participation in any thing relating to the society, not because he lives under a different law, but because his existence is not recognized by the society. His condition is not exceptional, for the law as a unity has no exception, but many parts. So, likewise, and on the other hand, where the individual by any means ceases to be a member, his right as a member to exercise the means of preserving his person and property ceases. It follows from the foregoing proposition, that society has no right to impose unequal burdens on any member, that any member has a right to the means of preventing it. That, while every member is bound to the extent of his ability to maintain and preserve the society, his obligation is limited by reference to the ends of society. That, to accomplish these ends, he must have a voice in the management of affairs, to be used for the preservation and well being, and not the destruction, of society. That, sharing the burdens, he is enabled to participate in the benefits of society, and vice versa. The parallel between a state and every other society might be still further extended. But sufficient has been said to illustrate the rule suggested. Now these same principles are equally applicable, if we consider an individual of one state, in reference to a foreign state. Then the diversity of rights is a part of the jus gentium. For example, an American is acknowledged by every European power as having rights, not only if he happens to be within its territorial limits, but even although he may never have entered them. The lex loci contractus will always prevail, except in those few cases in which the public law of the state where the contract is sought to be enforced may forbid. This branch of the law may be accurately termed the private international law. It is apprehended that the common term conflict of laws is altogether misapplied. Dr. Story's work on the subject is not a treatise on the conflict of laws, but on the agreement of laws. Where the law of one state is in conflict with that of another, it depends entirely upon the forum which law will prevail. It is only necessary to refer to that learned work to establish this opinion. The diversity of rights between the American and the Frenchman exists only so far as the law of the corporation renders the latter the possessor of, and denies to the other, certain corporate privileges. CHAPTER XII JOINT TENANCY This species of estate furnishes the most perfect instance of the principle of unity as applied to interest owned by two or more persons. It is one estate as to the state, as to the tenants, and as to third persons, being held by unity of time, title, interest, and possession. This unity can be destroyed a Common Law only by the voluntary act of the parties. Its relation to tenancy in common is identical with that of partnership to part-ownership, and it will be found, upon examination, that the principles of the former are generally applicable to joint tenancy. The jus accrescendi rests upon this ides, that each owns the whole estate, singulis in solidum debtur. Such, too, is the rule of partnership. Coke states that an alien can take as a joint tenant, and that the state cannot interfere until the estate has vested in him by survivorship, for the other tenant owns the whole fee, in solido, as he expresses it. It may be doubted whether this statement is correct. Undoubtedly the escheat cannot take place before survivorship, for the reason given; but if he were disseized by his cotenant, he would have been remediless. The enjoyment, therefore, of the usufruct would be altogether dependent upon the will of his cotenant. Moreover, by no manner of means could he acquire jurisdiction, for that is an attribute of the law, and the alien can take nothing by law, not even a usufruct for life. To admit him to be a joint tenant, in the legal signification of the term, would lead to the direct contradiction of some of the most certain rules of the law. He would have the right to bring a real action, to attend court as one of the pares, etc, etc; in short, to exercise those rights which, by the Common Law, were peculiar to citizens. A very serious practical difficulty would impede even the joint tenant who is a citizen, if he was forced to bring ejectment. Can he sue alone? The production of his title-deed would prove that he had a cotenant; if he joined him in the action, he would fail by reason of the alienage. But if the court should regard him, as in theory the unquestionably ought to be, as non-existing, then the same result would follow as if he were dead, the other would be sole owner. It was held by Lord Hardwicke, that where a legacy was left to two persons, in words that would make them joint tenants, if one of them died before the testator the whole passed in solido to the other, not by survivorship, but by force of the words, which made him sole owner. It is said that an alien may take, but cannot hold. Of course nothing more is meant than that, is long as the state does not interfere, he may enjoy the use and profits. The difference between him and a mere occupant without title is not very plain, for the latter may enjoy the use and profits until ejected by the party having the right. But neither the alien not the tortious occupant can be said to have the right. Besides, the occupancy of the latter will finally ripen into right, whereas that of the former never can resist the claim of the state. The idea of the jus adcrescendi is more correctly expressed in the phrase jus non decrescendi. "Dicitur etiam jus adcrescendi inter collegiatorios, et quod tamen magis est jus non decrescendi." This is manifestly true, for in the case, by way of example, of a joint tenancy, the survivor does not take the other half of the fee by the death of his cotenant; on the contrary, he had the whole during their joint lives, and it is not decreased by the death of the survivor. They have not, one of them a seizin of one half, and the other of the remaining half, but each has an undivided moiety of the whole, not the whole of an undivided moiety. This is what causes joint tenancy to differ from substitutions and remainders. In the latter, the survivor take that of which he had no seizin in the lifetime of the deceased. In the latter, one person is substituted in place of another; in the former the person is not changed. The rule being thus understood, and such clearly is its true meaning, it has a very extensive application in the law. Two joint tenants are una persona, and have unieum patrimonium, or one estate. So a corporation, a partnership, a family, a state, are each one person and possess one estate in apprehension of law. Death does not decrease nor increase the estate, nor destroy the civil person. CHAPTER XIII JUS ACCRESCENDI To the citizen alone was the privilege accorded by the Twelve Tables of declaring the testamentary law of his estate. Sovereign over his family, his individual will was the public law of the family, and prevailed over that of the family, the law of nature. This is also one of the distinctive characteristics of the Common Law. In the former, the identity of the civil person of the ancestor and heir was rigorously observed, so that, in the language of Papinian, una persona, unicum patrimonium. Hence, nemo potest pro parte testatus pro parte intestatus. The testator named only one persona as heir, which, however, might comprehend several individuals, to whom his whole estate passed per universitatem, as an entirety. Now in case one of the individuals to whom the estate was devised deceased, the other took his share. Because the will of the testator, having in early times been a law made by an ancestor in the assembly of the people, with their consent, repealed, as to his family, the general law of succession, and of course repealed it altogether; so that, to obey this private law, no part of the estate could pass to his next of kin. The share of the deceased was transferred to the survivor, to preserve at once the unity of the estate and effect the will of the testator. "Jus accrescendi est quia nemo simul testatus et intestatus recte moriebatur Romae". The Common Law has not adopted the rule that one cannot die partly testate and partly intestate, although it has received the jus accrescendi. The Civil Law maintained much more rigorously the unity of patrimony, and hence preferred the legatee to the heir by blood; whilst the Common Law favors the latter, or the diversity of patrimony. The Gallo-Romans knew nothing of testaments until the conquest by the Romans. There are, however, traces of a custom of transferring, in the lifetime of the testator, by way of sale, his property to a devisee, but limited to those cases in which the testator had no heirs of his body. The heir by blood was always preferred to the devisee, and a difference as to the classes of persons to whom they should descend was made between paternal and maternal inheritances. This was perfectly consistent with an exception to the rule, Nemo potest pro parte testatus, &c., that had been introduced into the Civil Law by Caesar, and perpetuated by Trajan, namely, that a soldier might die partly testate and partly intestate. After this time, the rule was thus propounded: "Nemo potest pro parte, testatus, pro parte intestatus decedere, nisi sit miles cujus sola voluntas in testando spectatur." The object of this rule was to enable the soldier to dispose of his "peculium eastrense" to one person, whilst his other property passed either to another legatee of a will made in solemn form, or descended to his heirs by blood. The diversity of patrimony was in exact accordance with the Gallic customs, so that when wills began to be used the military will was selected. It became the fashion of making a testament, and was again transmitted to the German tribes; for, as is said by learned Loysel, they comme gens de guerre ont reeu plusieurs patrimonies et divers heritiers diune meme personne. The Common Law has preserved the diversity of patrimony and the military will. But has also, as in all other instances, adopted the Civil Law rules of interpreting them. Hence, whilst the paternal and maternal inheritances descend to different heirs, yet, in reference to each class, the rule of jus accrescendi, or the unity of estates, is adopted. Regarding each class in itself, the rule is, Una persona, unicum patrimonium. CHAPTER XIV USUFRUCTS An estate for life is the lowest species of estate which requires livery of seizin. Littleton classes it with a term for years. "And the lessor is property where a man letteth to another lands or tenements for term of life for terms of years, or to hold at will, he which maketh the lease is called lessor, and he to whom the lease is made is called lessee." It was, however, regarded as a higher estate than terms for years, because the life estate conferred jurisdiction. A principality might be held for life, with dominion over its inhabitants. But in modern times, since the feudal system expired, and its traces in the law have been almost entirely obliterated form every portion of it, and altogether from estates for life, courts have regarded them merely according to their true nature. Setting aside all considerations as to jurisdiction, they have held that an estate for a number of years equal to those of human life was equivalent to a life estate. A term for life is only a term of tears equal to the duration of life. Supposing that terms for years were granted during the feudal age, the want of livery of seizin rendered the title insecure; the contract and its execution wanted the ordinary publicity of evidence of its existence. They were at the will of the parties, and might be annulled at pleasure. Hence they fell under the denomination of "precaria"; but as society advanced, and writing came into use, they became contracts cognizable in courts, whilst tenancy by sufferance and at will continued to be, as they are now, precaria. But even as early as the time of Fleta, that which was a tenancy at will, if verbal, was a term, if written; and daily observation shows that these precarious interests are now ripening into terms for a year. Now we have seen that Littleton classes life interests with terms for years, and that the law regards them as only equivalent to a term of years. We apprehend, therefore, that live estates, as well as terms for years, are properly usufruct interests in contradistinction to proprietary. They form the highest in that class, whilst by their ancient attribute of jurisdiction they unite the usufructuary class with the proprietary. Now a usufruct interest is a bailment, the relation of the parties that of letting and hiring, and in reference to property it is a chattel. The tenant for life has the rights and the duties which Domat states to be pertinent to the bailee; he should put the thing to no other use than that our which it was hired, he must commit no waste, he must restore it at the time appointed, do the service or pay the rent, and, in general, observe whatever is required by law, custom, or the contract. On the other hand, he is entitled to the profits. The correctness of Littleton's classification, and the truth of our remarks, are shown in his seventy-first section. There he states that, "if a house be leased to hold at will, the lessee is not bound to sustain or repair the house as tenant for term of years is tied." "For," says Coke, "the statute of Gloucester extends not to a tenant at will, and therefore for permissive waste the lessor hath no remedy." Now by that statues the lessor had an action for permissive waste against the lessee for life as well as for years. So that at Common Law neither the tenant for life, years, not at will, was bound to repair. That these were bailments appears from the concluding sentences of the sections of Littleton above cited: "But if a tenant at will commit voluntary waste, as in pulling down houses, &c., the lessor shall have an action of trespass against the lessee. As if I lend to one my sheep to taothe his land, or my oxen to plough the land, and he killeth my cattle, I may well have an action of trespass against him, notwithstanding the lending." And the reason is, says Coke, that when the bailee, &c. Now, it is apparent that a term of years, whether for life or for a certain number, is to that extent a diminution of the proprietors's usufruct interest in his estate. It is substantially a charge upon the principal estate, and, if no rent is paid, is of the nature of a vicum radium. Every usufructuary interest is the use and enjoyment of the property of another. Now the difference between a right to a usufruct interest in another's land, for a term of years equal to the duration of a life, and a right to use a part of another's land as a way for the same period of time, a right of way, is only in the mode of enjoyment. Both are usufructs, and both are onerous on the estate of the proprietor. A right to an easement may, according to its nature, belong to one or more individuals, or to one or more by virtue of their connection with a particular tenement. In either case the easement is a charge upon the servient tenement, and a benefit to the parties enjoying it. Now the rights of the parties entitled to the easement and the duties of the parties entitled to the easement and the duties of the party subject to it are identically those which we have seen pertain to the owner of a usufruct. The one is entitled to a full and free enjoyment of the easement without let of hindrance from the other, but he is not entitled to require the other, the bailer, or servient tenement, to repair. Thus the party entitled to a right of way cannot, in general, require the other to repair; if it becomes "foundrous," he must repair it himself or cease to use it, for he cannot go "extra vias," and travel over the adjoining land of the servient tenement, no more than the tenants of life could require the proprietor to repair. The statute of Gloucester, however, has altered the Common Law so as to compel the tenant for life to repair, but the owner of a right of way has not yet been compelled by statute to do so likewise. It is apparent, therefore, that the principles of the law which governs that extensive class of rights, the usufructuary, including estates for life, for years, at will, and sufferance, and the multitudinous variety of servitudes, are identically those of bailments. "I could not but observe with surprise," says Sir William Jones, in his preface to the Law of Bailments, "that a title which seems the most generally interesting should be the least understood and the least precisely ascertained. Hundreds and thousands of men pass through life without knowing, or caring to know, any of the numberless niceties which attend our abstruse though elegant system of real property, and without being acquainted with the exquisite logic on which our rules of special pleading are founded; but there is hardly a man who does not every day contract the obligations of a bailment; and what can be more absurd or dangerous that frequently to be bound by duties without knowing the nature or extent of them, and to enjoy rights of which we have no just idea?" CHAPTER XV EXECUTORY INTERESTS Gradually, as the feudal law declined, uses and trusts advanced in importance. Jurisdiction was lost in the fee, and became undistinguishable from it. The courts began to regard estates in reference to usufruct rather than to that which is of much more public interest, power. Regarding the life estates, as they were amply justified in doing, when disconnected with jurisdiction, as a mere chattel interest, a term for ninety-nine years was held equivalent for the support of a remainder to a freehold. And on this view, that estates are only usufructs, is founded the whole doctrine of executory devices. "An executory devices is strictly," says Mr. Fearne, "such a limitation of a future estate or interest in lands or chattels as the law admits in the case of a will, though contrary to rules of limitations in conveyances at Common Law." In a very early case it was held that a man might give a book (any chattel not consumed by use) to a person for his use during his life, and remainder over. Here, by distinguishing the usufruct from the legal property, a limitation directly contradictory of the rule of law was maintained. But no man can have in the nature of things more than a usufruct for life of any property or any power. The construction by which he has power over his estate after his death is not founded upon natural, but political reasons. It is the unity of jurisdiction that gives him the limitation to the heirs of his body, and declares that his heirs are so totally in him as a civil personage that he may give it to whom he will. Having, then, distinguished the usufruct from the legal estate, and thus avoided the rigor of the rule of law, all the canons of the doctrine of executory devises easily were deduced. Thus, as no man can have more than an enjoyment for life, if the use is limited to him and his heirs, and he dies, leaving no heirs living at the time of his death, there is no reason why another should not be named by the testator to succeed to the usufruct; or, as it is stated in the books, a fee may be limited after a fee. But it is proper to observe, that the use of the word fee either as expressive of jurisdiction or right at law is altogether erroneous; and, if taken in either sense strictly, would negative the existence of executory devices. Another corollary from the usufruct is, that an interest may be limited to commence in futuro. Commonly this is termed a freehold, but with a like disregard of correct language. It is not a freehold, which is a legal estate, but a chattel interest, and hence is consistent with the rule a Common Law by which a chattel interest may be made to commence in futuro. And lastly, because it is a chattel interest, it needs no particular estate to support it; whereas, if it were a freehold which required livery of seizin, it must have been preceded by a particular estate. There is another rule, that, where a limitation can be construed a remainder, it shall not be taken as an executory device; that is, where the testator does not express his intention clearly that his successors shall be regarded as usufructuaries, the public law attributes jurisdiction to the estates created. The public law must prevail over the private law of any subject. The misuse of the word freehold, in reference to usufructuary interests, has led to the difference of construction between the limitation of dying without issue, as applied to interests in lands and in chattels. It is admitted now that this difference is against grammatical construction, and the intention of the testator. Hence the courts have resorted to other, and perhaps as doubtful, verbal criticisms to overcome or avoid former precedents. These are followed, where they are in point. It may be observed, that the whole discussion no the rule in Shelley's case between Mr. Fearne and Mr. Douglas depends on the difference of the legal estate from the usufruct. Their difference, too, was merely verbal, the one contending for the intention of the testator, the other for the rigorous enforcement of the rule at law. Had they agreed at first, that they were or were not disputing about a legal estate or a usufruct, the controversy could have proceeded no further. The true nature of the interest is manifestly the substance of the question. Moreover, by resolving the question into its true elements, we are enabled to place the decisions, often seemingly contradictory, upon a solid foundation, and to reconcile them. The general law must be observed, unless the private lawgiver, the testator, exercises his power to make an exception from it by his own will, in such a clear and unequivocal manner as excludes doubt. So, in like manner, where a person has a power granted by a deed, his exercise of that power must clearly and unequivocally refer to its source; and if it does not, it will either transfer only such interest as he possesses, or be utterly void. In short, the rule in Shelley's case must be enforced, unless the testator has otherwise directed; but the person affirming the exception to exist must prove it. "The great and essential difference between the nature of a contingent remainder and that of an executory device consists in this; that the first may be barred and destroyed, or prevented from taking effect by several different means; whereas it is a rule that an executory devise cannot be prevented or destroyed by any alteration whatsoever in the estate out of which or after which it is limited." Certainly, when a limitation is admitted to be an executory devise, it cannot be barred; but that consequence of its nature does not, as Mr. Fearne states, explain its nature. It is a usufruct, the enjoyment of which depends upon a condition, and not a legal estate upon condition. A feoffment cannot operate except on strictly legal estates, and in such cases as might possibly have existed at the time when they were made in open court. As to usufructs, they are inapplicable, and when a conveyance made in that form has been recognized as of any validity of effect, it has been as a quasi conveyance under the statute of uses. The great and essential difference, therefore, between contingent remainders and executory devices is, that the former are limitations of legal estates upon condition, and the latter are limitations of the usufruct upon condition. A usufruct is a bailment, and there is no rule of law or reason which forbids a contract for the creation of a bailment at a future period, without a precedent bailment in some one else; not that a party may not enjoy a bailment to the end of his life, and then that it shall pass to another, or several others, upon condition; not that another may not, on a certain event, participate with the bailee in the enjoyment of it. In short, upon this fundamental distinction between legal estates and usufructs depend all executory interests in lands or in chattels. CHAPTER XVI POLITICAL STATUS Having traced the consequences in the law of real estate of the attribution to the landlord of sovereignty over his vassals or tenants, we are further to consider this principle in reference to personal rights. As has been before observed, no one in the feudal age, and therefore in the Common Law, held lands because he possessed political rights; on the contrary, he possessed political rights only because he was a landlord. Personal liberty existed, but the man who had no more was not the ilber homo of Magna Charta. His condition was inferior to that of the landlord, and he stood in the middle, between the lord and the villain. In short, the non- landholder had no political status; he was not what we term a citizen. In the documents of the Middle Ages, citizens were known as liberi homines, pares curiae, legales homines, and by various other titles, all of which meant that they were good men and true. These formed the basis of the whole organization, political, civil, and social and included every citizen, whether king or subject. The importance of this element of sovereignty the status civitatis has not been sufficiently developed, nor perhaps appreciated, by our juridical writers. Accurate digests of all the cases have been made, but neither their true reason nor the extensive ramifications of it seem to have been understood. This has arisen, probably, from the defective method in which they have treated of every portion of the Common Law. From Bracton, inclusive, they have in regular succession followed the arrangement of the Institutes of Justinian. In them, no notice is taken of the subject of citizenship, and for an adequate reason. By a series of laws, commencing at an early period of the Republic, the status civitatis was gradually bestowed upon the whole Roman world. An alien did not exist within its borders; therefore it was unnecessary for Justinian in a work intended merely to teach the neophytes of the law-schools at Berytum, Constantinople, and Rome, the rudiments of the law as it then existed to mention a subject only interesting to legal antiquarians. But it is far different in relation to the Common Law, and our writers have no excuse for their perfunctory method of treating of it. We will consider it first as it concerns the state, and then as it concerns the individual and the family, and the rights of property appertaining to these relations. It is necessary, for the elucidation of this topic, to premise a few things. In these States, every man has a right to vote, and thus to participate in legislation, without regard to his possession of property. But under the old Common Law, the right to impose taxes was confined to those who had property to be taxed. It was against its fundamental policy to permit person who did not share the burdens of taxation to impose them on his neighbors. Representation was inseparable from taxation, and taxation was always connected with representation. We use these phrases, familiar to us at present, to express the same principle that was contained in the phrase, the attribution of sovereignty to property. Again, it is to be also observed, that in every code of laws there are principles peculiar to that code, and others common to all civilized nations. For instance, the attribution of sovereignty to property was peculiar to our system; but the principles of the law of personalty are almost universal. It has been the practice adopted generally by nations, to confine the right to hold a part of their territory to citizens, and this has not been supposed to be detrimental to any of their important interests; whilst to extend that rule to personal property would manifestly cut them off from the society of nations. Now, the law of personal property is the law of nature, so far as it is cognizable in courts of justice. The Romans, and after them modern civilians, termed it the jus gentium, by which they meant that body of rules which are generally recognized by all civilized nations as obligatory upon individuals. It must not be confounded with the law of nations, or international law; nor, on the other hand, with that law of nature of which moralists treat. Touching the latter, it is to be observed that it is, as propounded by speculative writers, directly antagonistical to the Common Law. The latter maintains, as its fundamental principle, that property and its consequences, political power, are of positive institution. By it no man can affirm himself entitled either to property or power, except by the common consent of the state. The right to land does not spring from occupation, but from the grant of the state; nor has any man a right to possess a share of political power who has not previously obtained a share of its territory. These principles are, beyond doubt, inconsistent with the opinions most popular in this country. It is not our office to defend either side, and therefore we omit further notice of them. Blackstone has termed the law of nature the will of God. This may be admitted. Cicero had anticipated this view; for he declares that he will not argue with any man concerning the law, who denies the existence of God, and that he is the source of laws. But the important question is, How is that will to be known? Those who think that human reason is the true test of that will, easily arrive at conclusions which justify disobedience to all human laws. Assuming a state of nature once to have existed, in which all men were equal to all things were in common, it has been without difficulty deduced that property is robbery. It is not a little remarkable that the preachers of the law of nature include the most hostile classes of writers, the Christian and Deist. But all of them fortify their speculations by citations from the writings of the Roman lawyers who flourished under the Empire. At that time political rights were not only theoretically, but practically, denied, and no man save the Emperor could assert a right to his life, liberty, or property. Yet these lawyers agreed in these two fundamental propositions: "Quod ad jus naturale attinet omnes homines aequales sunt." "Ratio civilis jura naturalia corrumpere nequit." Their connection with the law of nature and its fruits, the doctrines which vex modern European society, is very plain. How, then, is the law of nature to be discovered? Revelation has disclosed to man the will of his Maker as to his internal life as an individual. His will as to nations, it is apprehended, will be discovered in those laws which prevail among civilized nations in all ages. These are the moral facts demonstrating his providence as certainly as any physical facts. The one is the physical law of nature, by speculation, anticipates these results, it deserves applause, but it does not constitute the test of their truth. They exist and are laws, whether discovered or undiscovered. CHAPTER XVII JUDICIAL OFFICE The author of Fleta Counsels the king, "Caveat sibi ne in sede judicandi quemquam loco suo substitnat inspientem et indoctum, corruptibilem vel severum." Can an alien sit in the seat of the sovereign? Whether sovereignty resides in one or many, sovereignty becomes subject by the delegation of jurisdiction to an alien power. The recognition by King John of the Pope as his feudal lord, which includes jurisdiction, was felt to be, and was resisted as, a violation of the fundamental law of the state. Indeed, such a doctrine never could have obtained the sanction of the descendants of the Norman conquerors. It is matter of history, that William took an oath to observe the native laws, but he committed the administration of them to his Normans, and speedily they were subverted. Jurisdiction could not, consistently with public safety nor the feudal law, be delegated to any but a member of the body politic. Certainly, before the separation of jurisdiction from property, no alien could have been a judge. That foreigners, in the troublous years that followed the death of the Conqueror, did occasionally occupy judicial places, is certain, but this was an incident of evil strife when laws were silent. Henry the First, in a capitulary, declared that "peregrimn very judicial, omnibus modis submovercuns." Such is the law of the present day; five centuries have produced no charge. The same is true also of every portion of the administration of justice. No alien can, by Common Law, be returned of juries for the trial of issues between the state and a subject, or between subject and subject. The jury de medietate is by statutory enactment. The objection that kings of England have been alien born, and have the power of appointing judges, is of no force; for the descent of the crown is per se an act of naturalization, and removes all the impurities from the fountain of justice. CHAPTER XVIII COURTS Among the earliest changes in the feudal system was the creation of courts, in which the feudal lord did not exercise jurisdiction in person, but by means of his delegates. But this transference of jurisdiction made no change in the principles upon which is was exercised. It was less summary, more formal, and more just. A feudal lord had jurisdiction only over his own vassals, and his own land; without both were subject to him, he could not decide the controversy. When the trial of causes relating to land was assigned to the court of Common Pleas, it also had jurisdiction only in case both vassals and land were within the territorial limits. Hence, as the lord could not try a cause concerning land in another domain, neither can that court an ejectment for lands in Ireland. Nor can it try a cause in which the king prosecutes a criminal, for that has been assigned to another court. Nor can the King's Bench try a land cause, nor a criminal whose offence has been committed out of the domain. In short, each court must possess competency as to persons and subject-matter, and all of them united possess all the jurisdiction that the feudal lord possessed. They are the delegates of the jurisdiction of the state. Hence, as they are delegates of the lord, they cannot derive jurisdiction from the consent of the litigants. They have it or have it not as delegates of the sovereign. Just as the vassal of one baron could not consent that his title to land in another baron's territory should be determined by the former. Under the feudal law, the recognition of the jurisdiction of another baronial court than that of which he was one of the pares, would have been punished by forfeiture, for it was a denial of his allegiance. Sequestration to compel appearance and foreign attachment by custom are merely devices to compel an absent party to submit himself to the jurisdiction, and do not impinge on the principles already mentioned. It was also a necessary consequence of the delegation of jurisdiction, that courts should so frame their modes of procedure as not to contradict the fundamental principle of their authority, competency as to jurisdiction and to property. It was not less necessary that this unity should exist in title to land, than in the court which was to determine a controversy concerning it. And this is equally true of all other courts, civil, maritime, naval, and ecclesiastical. They must possess competency as to persons and subject-matter. The observance of this principle has been strict, and is discoverable in the least important matters of special pleadings. Thus, in a real action, the venue is said to be local, and must be stated to be within those territorial limits which the ancient Court Baron, whose jurisdiction the Common Pleas now exercises, formerly supervised. So, likewise, in personal actions, the venue, though transitory, that is, many be alleged of any place, must be of some place within the territorial limits of the court. Jurisdiction over the person and the subject-matter must be united. It is apparent, therefore, that the same principle of unity which forms the basis of the political and territorial organization of the state, forms also the foundation of all courts, of their forms and rules of procedure. It concerns the greatest questions that can arise, without disregarding so petty a technicality as whether a venue shall be local or transitory. For the reasons already stated, the same controlling power is exercised by it over courts having the adjudication of crimes, and the imposition of forfeitures and punishments, their proceedings and their forms. The baronial courts never exercised what we term criminal jurisdiction. The distinction between public and private judges is found in the earliest period of the Middle Ages. Savigny has noticed the fact, that the compilations of laws made by the various conquering tribes were criminal codes, with a few provisions as to rights of property. They reserved to themselves, necessarily, the administration of public justice. Masters of the country by right of the sword, they had, even according to the Roman maxims, the criminal jurisdiction. The count, or by whatever other name the chief was called, recognized no distinction between his follower and his subject, as to crime, both were equally under the power of the sword. Between them, as to offenses, the difference was only in the degree of punishment. Hence it is that the public law of the feudal age differs altogether from the private, not only in principle, but also in its forms of procedure. In the former there is not the slightest trace of Roman law, in the latter it is always discoverable. CHAPTER XIX CITIZENSHIP It is evident from what has been said, that the citizen or landholder held, in relation to the non-landholder, a position of dignity and superiority. Savigny thinks that dignity is the proper word, and expresses accurately the idea of citizenship in the feudal age. "Thus there was one dignity common to all freemen, and a higher dignity confined to the nobility. The words dignity and freeman correspond to those of caput and ciris optimo jure among the Romans." He refers to the period of the Republic, when the patricians were distinguished from the plebeians rather by the antiquity of their origin than the importance of their privileges, and when the name of ciris was common to all classes of citizens. This dignity was carefully protected from usurpation by rendering it impossible for an alien to become a member of the community, except by obtaining the solemn and public consent of the sovereign, of state. This sentiment of the dignity of citizenship was, as we have seen, a striking trait in the character of the Germans, as well as of the Romans. The lord and the vassal, the noble and the plebeian, were equally proud of it. We have three remarkable historical instances in proof of this assertion. A barbarian, half naked and possessed of only the rudest arms, haughtily told Caesar, "Liberum se, libereque civitatis." The Apostle Paul, born of the despised race of conquered Judea, when about to be scourged by a centurion, said, "I am a Roman citizen," and "the chief captain when away afraid." A Roman Senator, Scipio, the second Africanus, being interrupted in the midst of a speech by the murmurs of a crowd of adopted citizens who stood around the tribune, struck them mute with the insolent exclamation, "Silence! ye bastards of Italy." The barbarian, the Christian Apostle, and the pagan Senator equally felt proud because they "had inherited the ennobling quality of original citizenship." We have quoted the words of a German who himself felt this sentiment, and who of all men that have lived in modern times best understood the character and history of Rome, Niebuhr. This common sentiment of the dignity of the citizen led among the German tribes, when they became landholders, to the establishment of rules for the protection of this dignity identical with those used by the Romans. Thus the slightest infringement upon his land was a great wrong; it was a trespass, although the trespasser had merely walked over uninclosed land. His house was his castle, and upon no pretence could be entered without his consent, unless the highest public interests required it. It was his castle, because, say Lord Coke and Gaius, "domus tutissimum cuique refugium atque receptaculum." His person was sacred, and he might put his assailant to death in case his own life was in peril. Such, also, is the rule of the Civil Law as stated by Gaius. A burglar might be put to death si nox furtum factum est, si eum aliquis occidisset jute cesus esto. A robber of a dwelling-house by day shall be beaten with rods, si luci furtum faxit. A robber by day, if armed and defends himself, may be killed, provided the assailed cries for help, si se telo defenset, quiritato, plorato que, post deinde, &c. In the early age of the Republic the creditor had what Lord Coke calls a personal lien, nexus, a mortgage of the person of the debtor, and might, upon his default in payment, have kept him as his slave or sold him. The gambling debts of the Germans were frequently paid in the same manner. The Common Law has adopted the modifications of the rule which was introduced in the time of Theodosius, by whom it was declared that imprisonment of a debtor for the smallest space of time was a full satisfaction: "Nec sane remuneratione precii debet exposcere cui, etiam minimi temporis spatio servitium satisfeeit ingenui." The dignity of the baron, the citizen, protected his family; a word including his estate as well as his wife, children, and dependents. Hence, to do an injury to his wife, either in person or character, or to his children, or to his servants, was his wrong. They, and their earnings and acquisitions, were his, and they could be vindicated only by him. Except through him, they had no rights of which the law took notice. The jurisdiction over his vassals was exercised by virtue of their possession of parts of his domain; but over his wife, children, and servants, because they were part of himself. CHAPTER XX ALIENS It is commonly said that an alien has capacity to take a fee simple by purchase, but not to hold it; and that he cannot even take by an act of law. The proposition would be more accurately stated thus: that by the Common Law lands can be holden only by citizens. It is not sufficient that the person be innocent of crime, or have paid the full value to the owner; he must also have the status. Nor is the exclusion of the alien a penalty upon the person for being born out of the ligeance; nor after he has purchased is the escheat in the nature of a forfeiture. On the contrary, in the judgment of law, the alien, so far as the holding of lands is concerned, does not exist, and the escheat takes place as if the last owner had deceased without heirs. It is indispensable that the person should be a member of the political community, free of the corporation, in order to enjoy any of its benefits. That land is holden only in virtue of political character is shown conclusively by the fact, that a native is not necessarily entitled to purchase and hold it. As where a villain, who in the Common Law is called natirus, "purchases in fee simple on in fee tail, the lord of the villain may enter into the land and oust the villain and his heirs for ever; and after, the lord may, if he will, let the same land to the villain to hold in villainage." So, where a freeman held lands by villainage, he had no political rights, did not participate in the administration of justice by courts, and differed in no respect form a villain. On the other hand, a villain who purchased lands, and held them by a free tenure, was, except as to the lord, a freeman. The villain, by manumission of his lord, became a citizen, as the alien does by naturalization. In both cases they acquire status on the same principle, adoption into the political family. This appears from the comments of Lord Coke upon the word enfranchisement: "it is derived from the word franchise, that is, liberty, and in the Common Law hath divers significations; sometimes incorporating of a man to be free of a company or body politic; sometimes to make an alien a citizen, and here to manumise a villain or bondman." The alien must receive the franchise of membership of the body politic. This could be obtained only with the consent of the sovereignty; that for the villain was his lord, for the alien, the state. A native freeborn man has now by the Common Law the common consent of all the members of the body politic, the status as his birthright. To hold lands, therefore, the person must be capable as well by the political parts as by the jus gentium of the municipal law. By the former by participates in theory in the administration of the affairs of the state. It is the union of jurisdiction and property which constitutes a perfect title to land. In the case of the alien these are severed, and hence he has no voice in the formation or administration of the law. He is not one of the pares curiae, and therefore cannot institute an action real or mixed; but having the benefit of the jus gentium, he may institute a personal action. But even this was denied him in the early age of the Common Law. The foreigners who visited England were generally merchants, and most of them Jews, and were save neither in life, liberty, nor property. The thirtieth chapter of Magna Charta, it is believed, is the first statutory enactment by which alien merchants obtained "salvum et securum conductum exire da Anglia, et venire, et morari et ire, tam per terram, quam per aquam," to buy and to sell. It is printed in all the editions of the statutes as of the ninth year of Henry II., but it is in fact a transcript from the roll of 25 Edward I., who at that time confirmed it. As late, therefore, as Edward I., none but merchants could visit England with safety. Other aliens, unless protected by a royal license, so far from acquiring lands and becoming feudal lords, entered the kingdom at the peril of their lives. No habeas Corpus existed to release them from the dungeons of the noble outlaw. Thus more than two centuries after the Conquest aliens were treated as enemies. The only modification of the rigor of this rule that has yet been made, is the permission of the alien to enjoy a lease of a house for habitation. This, too, is a judicial inference from the above-cited chapter of Magna Charta. So that, with this slight amelioration of his condition, the alien as to lands is as much under the ban of the law as when William the Conqueror enacted that "omnes liberi homines" should swear to defend his "terras et honores contra inimocos et alienigenos." In all ages of the Common Law, therefore, only citizens have had the capacity for the full enjoyment of all rights, political and civil. CHAPTER XXI GUARDIANSHIP The consequences of political status, as to the public and private rights of the individual, having been noticed, it is now to be considered in reference to the family. Nations have differed greatly in their laws as to paternal authority, but the feudal law recognized the relation between the father and his child only for political purposes. The father could not sell him into slavery, nor put him to death, nor control his conduct when he became able to do military service. As the heir apparent, he was treated with deference by his father's retainers, but he was still only the first of his vassals. It was as a vassal that he was known to the law. The duties of the lord to the vassal were to protect him in his person and estate. When the vassal, from any cause, could not render the services due, the lord might enter upon his lands and take the profits, either temporarily or perpetually; the right was suspended or determined. Temporary suspension by reason of the infancy of the vassal was wardship. Now it is manifest that the lord, king or noble, held towards his minor vassal a paternal relation. Guardianship, which by nature belongs to the father, by the feudal law belonged to the lord. The latter was entitled of right to the care of the person as well as of the estate of his young vassal. The person and estate, property and sovereignty, were inseparable, except in those instances in which the vassal held lands of several lords. In such case possession of the person game priority of right to its care and control. Thus the lord had over him paterna potestas, and was within his domain parens patriae. This power controlled his nurture, directed his education, his marriage, and thus, in a great measure, determined the course of his life. It is evident that, if an alien was the father, the law denied him every right that the law of nature confers upon paternity. Over the estate of his child he could nave no authority, not, as a consequence, over his person. The family relations, therefore, depended for their existence upon the approval of the public law. All human ties were as non-existent, whenever they came in conflict with the principle of unity of sovereignty and property. CHAPTER XXII COURTESY The guardianship of the wife by her husband necessarily gave him the management of her estate, and the enjoyment of its profits. It is only in an old and highly refined state of civilization that we discover traces of separate estates. The tenancy by courtesy unites, to a certain extent, guardianship and the institution of separate estate. This custom is said to have been introduced into England in the reign of Henry the First. This is extremely improbable, for the custom was well known in Normandy before the Conquest, and was too favorable to the husband to have fallen into desuetude. It may be that during that reign it first received judicial sanction; an opinion to which we incline, inasmuch as the cases referred to by our juridical writers are of a little later date. Traces of this custom may be found in the writings of the early portion of the Middle Ages. The Capitularies of Dagobert I. (A.D. 630) expressly mention it: "Si quae mulier quae haereditatem parernam habet post nuptum praegnans peperit filium, et in ipsa hora mortua fuerit, et infans vivus remanerit aliquanto spatio vel unius horae, haereditas materna ad paterm pertinet," &c. The same passage is found also in the Code of the Alemanorum, which, according to Savigny, was copied from the Bavarian. A capitulary was rarely limited to a single tribe, but usually extended to the whole people, and it is highly probable, therefore, that courtesy was generally prevalent. According to this passage courtesy was only the lands which the woman derived from he father by descent. This is the interpretation given to haereditas by Cicero: "Haereditas est pecunia quae morte alicujus ad quempiam pervenit jure nec ea aut legata testamento aut possessione retenta." Inheritance, in short, is by descent. In like manner a Roman magistrate presiding in Gaul, in the fourth century, writes to his legal friends in Rome this surprising fact, Gignantur haeredes et non scribuntur. This definition of Cicero is also implied in the Common Law rule that heirs take by descent, jure, for where they may take as heirs, they cannot take by purchase, The right by act of law jure is always higher than that by act of the parties. After the time of Cicero, haereditas received a wider signification, and meant inheritance acquired by devise as well as by descent. "Ac prius de haereditatibus despiciamus, quarum duplex condicio est; nam val ex testamento vel ab intestato ad nos pertinent." Courtesy is also mentioned, as we have observed, in the Bavarian Code, which was compiled A.D. 637. Savigny states that, in a multitude of passages, the imitation of the Roman law is evident, although the particular texts which have been followed cannot be indicated. He remarks, however, on the passage from the Bavarian Code, (which contains the custom of courtesy, and also refers to a provision for the wife after the death of the husband,) that he recognized in it two laws of Justinian, which grant to the survivor of the husband and wife an equal provision out of the profits of the estate of the other, and he cites these laws, But he observes also, that, while the law of Justinian allows this provision only in case the survivor is poor, the Bavarian Code takes no notice of this circumstance. It is not surprising, therefore, that courtesy should be found in the compilation known as the Petri Exceptiones Legum Romanorum. This work is supposed to have been written in the latter part of the tenth century (950-1000 A.D.). It contains a systematic exposition of the law as it then existed, and in a great degree of the Roman law. These are the words of chapter 33: "Si quis duxerit uxorem et dotem ab ea acceperit vivente uxore habeat omnes fructs dotis propter onera matrimonii. Ea vero defuncta siquidem nullos ex ea havuerit liberos, integro jure, &c. Si autem ex ea filios habuerit solum usum fructum habeat liberi autem proprietatem." Here, not only is the right of the husband to the enjoyment of the profits determined, but the distinction between the usufructuary and proprietary interests is expressly marked. It is noticeable, also, that Justinian allowed courtesy on account of the poverty of the husband; the Bavarian Code takes no notice of that fact, and the Petri Exceptiones gives the reason of the allowance of courtesy, propter onera matrimonii. Glanville, it is to be supposed, knew the latter work, for he published his treatise A.D. 1186. Yet he states that courtesy was confined to the maritagium, which is synonymous with dos, and in this respect is the same as the phrase paternam haereditatem in our citation from the Capitulary. Now maritagium in the old Common Law books meant only "the lands which the wife bringeth in frank marriage." But it is not probable that Glanville used it in that limited sense, unless we suppose that he, the chief justice of a Norman prince, was ignorant of the laws and customs of the Normans. If it was first introduced into England by Henry, he derived it from Normandy, and during his reign Glanville wrote. We suppose, therefore, that Glanville used the word maritagium in a sense comprehending all the lands of the wife. The Ancien Coutumier of Normandy allows courtesy in all the lands of the wife, toute la terre, of which she was seized at the time of her death. It is probable, however, that this contracted meaning of the word maritagium, as well as the nation that the husband could not be entitled unless he was poor, a lackland, did find acceptance among the civilians of that age. We say civilians, for the latter idea was to be found in none of the customary codes, but was mentioned by Justinian, and only by him. To correct these errors, Bracton enters into details otherwise unnecessary. He propounds the rule thus, that the husband, whether he had or had not an estate, was entitled to courtesy if he married a wife having "haereditatem, maritagium, vel aliquam terram ex causa donationis." Adding to this summary the word dotem (which is, however, synonymous with maritagium and therefore unnecessary to the sense), we have in this passage an epitome of the three citations that we have made. Further, the Capitulary recognizes the distinction between paternal and maternal inheritances. By the Common Law if a man marries in inheritrix of lands in fee simple, who has issue a son, and the son enters as heir to the mother and than dies without issue, the heirs of the mother shall inherit, and not those of the father, for paterna paternis, materna maternis. Then, in the example of courtesy put by Littleton, upon the death of the wife and the issue, the lands ought immediately to have descended to the heirs according to the rule materna maternis. But, on the contrary, it is disregarded and an exception made in favor of the husband by courtesy propter onera matrimonii. The use of the word courtesy in the sense of a rule of law is not peculiar to black letter; thus, "The courtesy of nations allows you my better, in that you are the first-born." When the reason ceased, where there was no issue, then the national sentiment, Dotem non uxor marito, concurred with the interests of the maternal heirs in enforcing an observance of the general rule of descent, materna maternis. Such, then, is the origin of this doctrine, and the reason that tenancy by courtesy, to the requisites of its corresponding estate, dower, namely, marriage, seizin, and death, adds that of issue. As it does not differ from dower in reference to jurisdiction, we shall postpone our remarks on that topic to the chapter on Dower. CHAPTER XXIII DOWER There are four kinds of dower de la plus belle could be obtained only by the judgment of a court, and its purpose was to prevent the division of lands which were subject as a unit to military service. In like manner, there cannot be partition or endowment of a castle held pro defensione regni. Dower ad ostium ecclesiae is in fact a jointure, which after the death of the husband the wife may refuse, and be endowed at Common Law. Coke observes that it could be granted only at the door of the church, because in this and like matters the law requires publicity and solemnity. So in the early ages of the Common Law all feoffments were made in the presence of the pares curiae. Deeds executed by the parties were altogether unknown, for few of the priests, and fewer of the lords, could sign their names. But as the transfer was made in the presence of the vicinage, it had, as in cases of dowment ad ostium, all necessary publicity and solemnity. To perpetuate the proof of these contracts, it was customary to make a memorial of them in the chartulary or ledger-book of some adjacent monastery. Dowment made at the door of the church, under the patronage of the guardian saint, was in all probability duly entered in like manner by the priests. Mr. Turner has published such a memorial or marriage settlement in his valuable History of the Anglo-Saxons. This kind of dower was also known in Normandy. Dower ex assensu differs altogether from dower at Common Law. It is not assigned out of the husband's lands and tenements, but out of the father's or brother's; and the right to it is by act of the parties, and not by act of law. It is, like the ad ostium, a jointure, and must be created by deed. From the fact that a deed is indispensable, it is certain that it must be of comparatively late introduction into England. All the authorities cited by Coke are of the age of Bracton, about two hundred tears after the Conquest, and as that was the most flourishing period of the Civil Law in England, it may also be inferred to owe its origin to that system. This species was well known to the Lombards, under the name of faderfium. The word of the Lex Rotharis, as cited by M. la Ferriere, are these: "De faderfio autem id est,de alio dono quantum pater aut frater dederit ei quando ad maritum ambulaverit." A.D. 643. The Franks also used this species of dower. Marculf, a Frank, and a monk of the diocese of Paris, compiled in A.D. 660 a book of forms. Among them is the precedent of a deed to create dower ex assensu, libellus dotis. Savigny refers to this work as a "most precious compilation," containing indisputable evidence of the wide-spread influence of the Civil Law in the Middle Ages. On the other hand, all the Common Law writers on the ancient feudal tenures cite his formula as authority. The Petri Exceptiones mention it under the name of propter nuptias donatio. Chap. 33: "Propter nuptias vero donatio, defuncta uxore, in patrimonio mariti revertitur, et inter alios res ejus computatur." The Ancien Coutumier of Normandy also contains the same law. Civilians are agreed that the ante-Justinian law prevailed during the Middle Ages, and that the compilations of Justinian were unknown. The changes, therefore, which were made in the character of the propter nuptias donatio did not affect the Gallo-Roman provinces This donatio, says Mahlenbruch, existed originally apud orientes, and was introduced into the Roman law by Constantine, A.D. 319. From Rome in passed to the provinces, and was adopted by the German conquerors. Their works of mixed law have transmitted it to us. CHAPTER XXIV DOWER AT COMMON LAW Tacitus states that the custom of the Germans was, that the husband endowed the wife; and in this respect they differed from the Gauls, who required mutuality of gifts, and from the Romans, who united the Gallic custom with that of the wife endowing the husband. But it must not be supposed that Tacitus, in the sentence often cited by our juridical writers, "dotem non uxor marito, sed uxori maritus," referred to dower at Common Law. For the next sentence he states that the parents or friends of the wife were always present to give their approval of the presents: "Ittersunt parentes et propinqui ac munera probant." It was, in fact, a jointure, and if not satisfactory, the marriage did not take place. Dower was known to them, however, under the name of morgengabe, and to the Saxons as morgengift, both words meaning the gift of the morning after the marriage. The consummation of the marriage evidently was necessary, and our Common Law writers plainly state that is was the "praemium pudoris." The Ancien Coutumier also gives the same reason; au coucher gague la femme son donaire. The dower of the wife differed in quantity among the tribes, but the Franks, Burgundians, and Saxons allowed her one third part de omui re quam simul collaboraverunt, de eo quod vir et mulier simul conquiererint. It was originally the wife's share of the land which she and her husband had jointly labored for or conquered. Now the Germans in their military emigrations were always accompanied by their wives, and their settlements were made, not as soldiers, but as tribes. As long as the husband and wife lived, they enjoyed together, to use the energetic expression of the Saxon law, their common conquest. Not only do their compilations of laws prove that this custom arose after their invasion of the Roman provinces, but it could not have arisen before; for, as they had no private estates in land, there could be no dower. Indeed, their first appearance on the banks of the Rhine was as fugitives seeking escape from more powerful tribes. When, finally, they broke into the provinces, it was still by compulsion, being driven onwards by adverse fortunes in the wars which seem always to have vexed the regions whence they came. The Normans seized upon a protion of France in the ninth century, about four hundred years after the first invasion of the Germnan tribes. They adopted the customs of the Franks in a great measure, and allowed the wife one third as her dower. Littleton, in his thirty-sixth section, has copied almost verbatim the ancien Costumier: "Coutume est que la feme qui a son mari mort, ait la tieree partie du fief au temps quil epousa." All the tribes condemned marriage with an alien. In A.D. 370, the Emperors Valentinian and Valens prohibited, under the penalty of death, the marriage of citizens and barbarians. The rigor of this law was afterwards so modified as to permit such marriages with royal license. At length, however, Alaric became king of the Visigoths, and, assuming to himself and his barbarians the name of Roman citizens, revived the law in all its severity. His code declares that al lawful marriage can be contracted only between Roman citizens; "Legitimae sunt nuptiae, si Romanus Romanam," etc. Again, a Roman citizen cannot be in the power, as a ward, for instance, of homo peregrinae conditionis. Indeed, the Breviarium only expresses the universal sentiment and custom of the tribes. The full force of this prohibition can only be estimated by considering that in that age, and long afterwards, the conquerors and the conquered had not amalgamated. They lived in the same villages, upon adjoining farms; met daily and traded together; were mutually indebted for the various services of civility and humanity that contiguity produces; but marriage was impossible. A want of status, whether by reason of alienage or bondage, rendered marriage infamous. CHAPTER XXV MARRIAGE If a man seized of a fee in lands taketh an alien to wife and dieth, she shall not be endowed. Marriage, therefore, does not communicate to an alien woman all the rights that it does to a native freeborn woman. Now Coke states that the only three requisites to entitle a woman to dower are marriage, seizin, and death of the husband; yet though the alien woman is married, and her husband hath seizin and dies, she shall not be endowed. It is clear, then, that the marriage meant is that between citizens. That there is an important difference between the marriage of citizens and that of a citizen and alien is made very manifest by this: that if a marriage be avoidable by divorce in respect of consanguinity, yet if the husband die before divorce, the wife shall be endowed; for this is legitimum matrimonium, quoad dotem. Here we see that an incestuous union, if not annulled in the lifetime of the husband, is a legitimate marriage de facto, not de jure, as to dower. But quoad dotem, the alien woman did not contract even a marriage de facto. In England divorce is exclusively within the jurisdiction of the ecclesiastical courts, and in the case above stated the death of the husband prevented a sentence of divorce, death had anticipated ecclesiastical censure. Hence the judge returns a certificate of legitimum matrimonium. But the death of the husband absolutely debars the alien wife from her claim of dower. Bracton mentions the justum et legitimum matrimonium, but does not explain or define it. Indeed, our juridical writers afford us no assistance. However, marriages, as we have seen by the citation from Coke, may be de facto or de jure, and of course there is a difference between them. In both cases the parties must be able, willing and do consent. These may be termed the requisites of the jus gentium. Our system adds that of citizenship in every contract relating to land. It is evident, then, that the legitimum matrimonium cannot be contracted de facto or de jure by an alien. For marriage in either case would have conferred upon her a full participation on all the rights of the husband. That such was the result of a legitimate marriage appears from the definition of it in the canonical law: "Viri et mulieris congunctio, individuam vitae consusctudinem, cum divini et humnani juris communicatione, continens." Furthermore, it is to be considered that, in the earlier ages of the Common Law, land was almost the only species of property. To deny to the alien wife, therefore, any share of it, was a practical denial of all rights of property. Yet this was done by a system which recognized the right to dower as not only a legal and equitable, but also a moral right. So that the law did not recognize her existence at all in any civil or moral capacity. Moreover, dower was avowedly allowed propter onera matrimonii et ad sustentationem uxoris, de facto or de jure. She, therefore, who was not entitled to it was not a wife. It is to be observed that although aliens, male or female, have the capacity by the jus gentium to acquire lands, they are prevented by defect of political status. Being subject to the former, they may by descent of purchase acquire that kind of property regulated by that law, personalty. Here, again, we recognize the principle of unity and the correspondence of persons and property. The legitimum matrimonium of the Common Law is identical with the connubium of the Civil. That could not take place between slaves, not a slave and a free person, nor, except by license, between the alien and a citizen. Such, too, is the Common Law in regard to the first two instances. And as to the last, we learn that, by a special act of Parliament, all women aliens who from thenceforth should be married to Englishmen by license of the king might demand dower. Connubium was also termed justum aut legitimum matrimonium, justae nuptice, in contradistinction to contubernium. The latter was not regarded as mere concubinage. It differed from connubium in this respect, that it conferred upon the wife no political equality with the husband, nor any participation in his religious observances of civil rights. On the other hand, connubium is exactly defined by the canonical definition of marriage. It was peculiar to citizens. "connubium inter cives; inter civem autem et peregrinae conditionis hominem aut servilis non est connubium sed contubernium." The maxim of the Common Law, "Consensus non concubitus facit natrimonium," was received as true only in reference to this species of marriage. But under the influence of Christianity, although the distinction between the civil contract and the sacrament was not entirely obliterated, the Church considered consent as marriage between an alien and a citizen. As the connubium was peculiar to citizens, so was the marriage ceremony of a corresponding character, There were three kinds of nuptial ceremonies, and two of them, usus and confarreatio, have some resemblance or analogy to the practices of modern times. The usus was where the wife domiciled with her husband for the space of a year, without being absent for three nights. The other, confarreatio, was the most solemn, The marriage was contracted in the presence of the father or guardian and of witnesses, before the altar, and accompanied with a sacrifice by a priest. By this form the wife became subject to the power of her husband, in manum reniebat. Hence the rule that he acquires the property of the wife, "quam in manum ut uxorem receperimus, ejus res as nos transeunt." Its coincidence in form and consequences with our mode on contracting lawful marriage is remarkable. In the early times of the republic all citizens and priests used it alone. When, however, Grecian manners had corrupted Rome, this, with many other ancient customs that had, fortunately for us, previously been adopted by the Germans, fell into desuetude. We apprehend, therefore, that an alien woman could not contract with a citizen justum et legitimum matrimonium either by the Civil or Common Law. Nor, indeed, by the canonical law, unless we suppose that, by the phrase humani juris, only natural law is intended. That many be the correct view, as it is derived form the Justinian law, and in his age citizenship and humanity were coincident. The jus gentium was the law of the Empire. CHAPTER XXVI CONVEYANCES There existed in the feudal law, as we have seen a correspondence of persons and property, the result of a attribution of sovereignty to the landed proprietor. The Germans, say Savigny, had a species of perfect property like the dominium ex jure quiritium of the Romans. Of course he means that in the Middle Ages, after their conquests, they had such property, for before that time, as has been frequently observed, they had no private estates in land. It could be held only by citizens. "Aut enim ex jure quiritium unusquisque dominus erat aut non intelligebatur dominus." The ennobling quality of citizenship was his right to hold it. It is not surprising, therefore, that citizens should have peculiar modes of transferring this perfect property. The Common Law had only three original kinds of conveyance, feoffment, exchange, and partition. Exchange is, in fact two conveyances, and might therefore be properly removed from the class of original conveyances. Our remarks on the subject of feoffment are equally applicable to exchange. Feoffment was known to the Romans and Gallo-Romans under the name of cessio in jure. The latter was employed to transfer, not only lands and things savoring of realty, but also slaves. Gaius gives the most precise directions for the mode in which it should be made. "in jure cessio hoc modo fit; apud magistratum populi Romani velut Praetorem vel apud praesidem provinciae is cui res in jure ceditur rem tenens its dieit. Hunc ego (hominem, fundum) ex jure quiritium meum aio, deinde postquam hic vindieaverit, praetor interrogat eum qui cedit an contra vindicet. Quo negante aut tacente tunc eu qyu vubducaverutm ean ren addicit." This is the exact method in which a feoffment at Common Law was made. It was executed in open court, the demandant or grantee claiming a piece of land, the defendant or grantor by agreement assertion or being silent, and the magistrate giving judgment for the demandant. The memorial which was made of the transfer was termed transactio, and had the authority of res judicata, for every person who could clam any interest in the land was one of the pares curiae, and in apprehension of law was present at the time the feoffment was made. His silence was consent. Hence the consequences of this mode of conveyance, which destroys all contingent estates, limitations, and conditions. When the feoffment was executed in a court of record it was termed a Fine. That the feoffment was used to transfer incorporeal rights as well as lands is shown by this circumstance: that, in a suit for an sdvowson, the demandent used the words of Gaius above cited. Mr. Reeves has given a procedent of such a declaration. Parition by decree of a court, or adjudicatio, was another species of conveyance, peculiar to citizens. The action, "quae discitur familiae heriscundae locum habety inter eos qui communem haereditatem, &c., et inter cohaeredes ubi agitur de proparte sororum vel inter alios ubi res inter partes et cohaeredes dividi debeat," &c. The Roman Law had also an action de communi dividudo, which differed so little from the former, familiae heriscundae, that it was thought by the compilers of the digest unnecessary to treat of them separately. "Adeo affines sunt, ut de his simul agere necessarium." Coke in the above extract does not notice this distinction, and treats these two actions as one. The Digest explains that the actio familiae is "actio quae cohaeredi adversus cohaeredes datur ut dividatur haereditatem. Actio autem communi dividundo est actio quae inter eos qui quascunque res praeter haereditatem communes ac indivisos habeat datur ut illae res inter eos dividantur." At Common Law, as in the Civil, the actio familiae is exclusively applicable to coparceners or coheirs. They derive their name from the fact that they may, whilst tenants in common and joint tenants cannot at Common Law, be compelled to make partition. The word heriscundce is a corruption of the word ercendo, the ancient form of coercendo, from coerceo, to compel. Gaius states that this action was derived from the law of the Twelve Tables, "de haereditatibus et de tutelis." The Common and Civil Law continue in all the consequences of this mode of partition to be identical. Thus, there must be equality of partition, each warrants the share of the other. Where the property is indivisible it is given to one, subject to the payment to the other of the value of his share. In like manner, both systems recognize partition by lot and arbitrament. Littleton mentions that other incident of partition known as Hotchpot. The Common Law confined it to land given in frank marriage. In the Civil Law it comprehended every advancement of the father to his child, and was known as the collatio bonorum. Domat discusses the whole subject with his usual ability and learning. CHAPTER XXVII POSSESSION "To suppose a state of man," says Chancellor Kent, "prior to the existence of any notion of separate property, when all things were common, and when men throughout the world lived without law or government, in innocence and simplicity, is quite fanciful, if it be not altogether a dream of the imagination." The learned author then goes on to state, that occupancy is the natural and original method of acquiring property in lands and movables. Certainly the Common Law rejects all such notions, and holds property to be of positive institution and not derived from any other source. Our system does not permit us to enter into the refinements which the modern civilians discuss, as to the question whether occupation does or does not confer a right. All lands belong either to the state on an individual, and the occupant without title is a trespasser. The lapse of time will not bar the remedy of the former, but it will of the individual, and in the latter case only by virtue of positive legislation. Until the remedy is completely barred, the occupant is as much a trespasser as he was at the moment he entered upon the land. Moreover, the public law interferes not for the sake of the individual, but to preserve the public peace; the advantage to the occupant is incidental. There are questions growing out of the loss of remedy to the rightful owner, which, it is believed, have not yet been settled by judicial opinion. Thus, where a person by adverse possession can defend himself against the true owner, if he dies without heirs, shall the land escheat to the state, or does it revert to the former rightful owner? Is the right to the land extinguished, or only the remedy for its recovery taken away, by the statutes of limitation? In the analogous case of a debt, although the remedy may be barred, yet the right to the money, the consideration, still exists so far that a new promise will receive the right of action. There are numerous other cases in which the same rule is admitted. A principal difficulty in the way of considering the right as unextinguished is that interpretation of the statutes of limitation concerning lands, which makes them, not only means of defence, but of acquisition. But that view is founded upon the assumption that there is a law of nature which justifies man in occupying lands within the territory of an established state. It is a law, however, that is not tolerated where the public is concerned. The Civil Law recognized three kinds of occupation, that with just title, that with a supposed just title, and, lastly, mere tortious occupation. By that system these three classes had appropriate and specific remedies. And the division is manifestly not without some show of reason. But the Common Law notices only the first and last of them. The word possession is used by our legal writers to express, not only the occupation of a rightful owner, but also that of a wrong-doer, the pedis possessor. But it is apprehended that it is properly applicable only to the former, and certainly has that grammatical sense. The possessor, by whom is meant the rightful owner, has, 1. A right of property; 2.Occupation by himself, or his agents or tenants. To acquire the first, contract is necessary; to acquire the second, investiture or livery. Livery is continually confounded with seizin by writers, but they differ as much as cause end effect; it is by livery that seizin is obtained. The possession of a feud is seizin, possession is synonymous with seizin. It is in this sense that Britton states that a frank tenement is the possession of a feud. The right of property, together with actual occupation, was not sufficient to make a frank tenement; investiture also was indispensable. Investiture was an act of sovereignty, whether is concerned the creation of a principality, a title of honor, or a tenancy in fee simple. It was the solemn and public delivery of the land, an approval of the contract by the sovereign, whether king or lord, in the presence of the peers of the person to whom it was granted. Hence, if a person having acquired the right of property entered upon the land without investiture, he was a trespasser. His entry might be clandestine, clam, secretly, and the remedy was, as Bracton states, a writ of intrusion, which might be purchased when one ratione alicujus chartae entered without livery. The Civil Law was in this respect identical with the Common Law. Bracton uses the very words of that system. Domat states, that if a person who had acquired a title entered upon the land clandestinely, that is, without the knowledge of the person by whom opposition might be made, he was a wrong-doer. It is not unimportant now to have a correct knowledge of these principles. For although the solemn form of investiture is no longer observed, yet the substance of it still remains. Inattention to them will certainly lead into error. We will show this, and at the same time elucidate some of the leading rules of the law of descents. Mr. Reeves, in his History of the Common Law, a work of considerable authority, states that seizin was merely possession, meaning thereby occupation. So that a tortious occupier had possession or seizin. Nothing can be more incorrect than this statement; feudal history and judicial authority contradict it. Again he states, "that another (possession) was a precarious and clandestine possession attended with violence." Passing by the contradiction of a clandestine possession attended by violence, he plainly confuses three different kinds of occupation, the precarious, the clandestine, and the violent, precaria, clam, vi et armis. The last two, moreover, are acquired against the consent, and the first with the permission, of the true owner. "Item est quaedam possessio precaria ut si quis concesserit alieui habitationem," &c. To this class originally belonged, as we have seen, tenants for years, at will, and by sufferance. It followed necessarily from this error, that Mr. Reeves should not understand, not only the rules, but the history, of the Common Law. Another illustration of the consequence of neglecting the fundamental principles of the Common Law will be found in the criticism of Mr. Stephens in the explanation given by Mr. Blackstone of the maxim, "Non jus sed seisina facit stipitem." The former remarks that the solution of the latter is unsatisfactory. The passage of Blackstone is in these words: "We must also remember that no person can properly be such an ancestor as that an inheritance of lands and tenements can be derived from him unless he hath actual seizin of such lands, either by his own entry," &c. Mr. Stephens says that the origin if this rule has never been satisfactorily traced, and that, though Blackstone's explanation may sufficiently show why the descent was not derived except from a person who had obtained actual seizin, yet it does not show why the person seized was to be propositus or root of the descent in preference to a purchaser who has obtained actual seizin. For instance, suppose this case: A dies seized, leaving B his heir; now if B dies without having obtained seizin, the heir of A, and not of B, will inherit the estate. Here B, being next in blood, might obtain seizin, but, failing to do so, he does not become the propositus. If to this case we add another element, and suppose that B, in his lifetime, conveyed his right to a bona fide purchaser, who enters into actual occupation, and then B dies, never having had seizin, Mr. Stephens informs us that the heir of A has the right to enter and eject the purchaser, and that the reason of this is unexplainable by himself or Mr. Blackstone. The difficulty in the solution of the question consists solely in this, that, like Mr. Reeves, they confound seizin with actual occupation. Actual seizin is their phrase. But seizin consists of three things, the right of property, actual occupation, and the consent of the lord. When a person has seizin in this sense, he is the propositus. The purchaser in the case put had the right, the actual occupation, but not investiture; and without the latter, occupation with right did not constitute a good title. In the language of the maxim, "Non jus sed seisian facet stipitem." For example, suppose the case of a tenant who conveys his feud to another; although this contract was obligatory between them, the purchaser could not enter without the consent of the lord under whom the tenant held. Again, in the same way, and no other, is to be explained the maxim, "Possessio fratris de feodo simplici, facet sororem haeredem." It is only necessary to observe that the phrase possessio de feodo simplici is a paraphrase of the word seisina. Now upon these two maxims nearly the whole Common Law of descents depends. Mr. Brown in his work on the leading maxims of the law, mentions only one other on this branch, "Haereditas non ascendit." This implies the existence of the fires that we have noticed, and is only indicative of the person who may demand seizin. Misapprehension, therefore, of the true reasons of these maxims cannot but prevent satisfactory explanations of questions of law. "The reason of the law is the life of the law; for though a man can tell the law, yet, if he know not the reasons thereof, he soon shall forget his superficial knowledge. But when he findeth the right reason of the law .... this will not only serve him for the understanding of the particular case, but of many others." Investiture did not confer jurisdiction. The law attributed jurisdiction to property, and that without the intervention either of the donor or the donee. The omission to distinguish between this attribute and the investiture has conduced to, of it has not altogether produced, the confusion which we have heretofore noticed as existing in the use of the word fee. After the lord had created a limited estate, he still retained jurisdiction; and if we suppose that the tenant of the limited estate made a subinfeudation, he also had jurisdiction over his sub-tenant. Thus, in regular succession from the sovereign to the lowest baron, jurisdiction belonged to the donor. Every feud was a miniature copy of the state. CHAPTER XXVIII RETROSPECT The inquiry which we have made has exhibited the fact that the Common Law in all its parts, political, civil, and social, rests upon the principle of the attribution of sovereignty or political power of the proprietors of land. They alone possessed a voice in the government, the right of representation, of imposing taxes, of holding high places. The non-landholder was impotent. Time has greatly modified this law, even in England; but property is still there the source of power. In this country much has already been done to take away all direct influence from property; its indirect influence, in the shape of corruption, must continue, and history teaches us that it will increase, as population becomes more dense. The utility of this change, from the direct to the indirect, the wisdom of reversing the Common Law rule of attribution power to landed property, are question without the scope of the present inquiry. But it may be observed that, as the bottom, they really resolve themselves into the question of the best form of government. A great statesman, lately deceased, has stated with great clearness and force the arguments in favor of the concurrent majority, the union of numbers and taxation, power and property. His disquisitions are not, in this respect, novel in theory, but old, and approved by the experience of a great and happy and highly civilized people. But in may, nevertheless, be utterly inconsistent with the very different form of government under which we live. Right or wrong, it does present for our consideration the gravest question which can employ the thoughts of any people. It is also to be observed, that in proportion as this principle has ceased to be practically operative in the law, will the legal system of these States differ from the ancient Common Law. We may continue to term it the Common Law after the attribution of jurisdiction to property is no longer remembered except by antiquarians, but it will not be the Common Law. A New system, having different basis, tendency, nature, and results, will grow up; and if it is cultivated with the aid of English books which recognize as a fundamental principle what is rejected by us, our system must be bent from its natural tendency, and so be deformed. That American law may perhaps be better calculated than its original to protect man in the development of his moral and mental qualities. Under its shadow he may enjoy, in larger proportion than his ancestors, those blessings which good laws and good government defend, but do not create. But these are not certain results. Even the advocates of human perfectibility do not contend that an entire departure from the experience of the past is either desirable in itself or proper to attain their promised condition of perfection. They teach the possibility to human development reaching perfection, not the necessity of complete revolution, either in public or private law. Moreover, the private law must, in a greater or less degree, be assimilated to the public. "At jus privatum sub tutela juris publici," says Lord Bacon. Then it is not less a momentous question to individuals, What will be the consequence to private property of the recognition of the principle that political power does not belong to property? Some bold theorists have already announced the consequences; and, admitting it to be true that numbers, the majority, are the rightful owners of the power of the state, it will be difficult to refute the inference that they may dispose of the whole state, and therefore of every part of it. Power is human will, applied to things is creates property, and has the masterdom and disposition of it. Why, then, should the rightful owners of the power, the life, of the state, not participate in the property which sustains that life? Why should the state not feed upon the property of the state? All men are equal, one generation cannot bind another, governments may be changed at pleasure, the majority can do no wrong. These are principles which seem not uninteresting to the possessors of property. It is possible that the fundamental maxim of the Common Law is unjust to mankind. Certainly the architects of it did not intrust the preservation of property to those who might have an interest in its destruction. CHAPTER XXIX THE TENDENCY OF THE AMERICAN LAW The British Colonies in North America were connected together by a common allegiance to one crown, and in reference to it they were one people. Their internal condition also tended towards unity. From their first settlements they possessed the manners, knowledge, and refined modes of thought which belong to a highly improved state of civilization. They knew no barbarous age in which the grams of their institutions originated. They had brought with them from the mother country the general principles of free government and the leading maxims of her jurisprudence. They all adopted them, with such modifications as a change of country required. No dissimilarities existed or grew up among them, such as distinguish the Scotch or Irish or Welsh from the English. The inhabitants were almost altogether alike, with some shades of difference in matters of religion; but sectarian dispute had never been inflamed into civil strife. Hence, when they threw off their political allegiance, the Puritan and his antagonist, the Episcopalian, the Roman Catholic and the Huguenot fugitive from roman Catholic power, freely and voluntarily pledged to each other their lives and sacred honor to accomplish a revolution that should establish a free government, which, whilst it tolerated every form, denied, what each had aimed to attain, superiority to any form, of sectarianism. This fact alone proves incontestably, that in heart, customs, laws, institutions, and political principles, the inhabitants of the provinces were one people. The Articles of Confederation, therefore, had no such difficult task to perform as had the laws of the Middle Ages, or if Edward the Confessor, to blend diverse gases, who had never before stood face to face but as foes, into one harmonious people. The revolt of the Colonies disturbed, but did not destroy, the internal governments and established laws of the States. The Articles supplied partially the want of a common political tie. And when experience let to their abandonment, it was not because the internal, but the external, relations of the States required it. Undoubtedly, as they operated only upon the States in their collective capacity, and could not directly affect the people, they created a government weak at home and abroad. In legal formula, it may be said that the fiction of the unity of the federal government had for its basis the fiction of the unities of each State. This was the defect in the Confederation of 1871. The ninth article, which contains all the provisions of the settlement of questions between the States and between individuals, makes no alterations in the private laws of the States. These were unchanged. The Constitution of 1787, which was intended to correct the defects of the Articles of Confederation, and to form a more perfect union, invests the general government with jurisdiction over the States, and in certain cases over the people of the States. But is does not, nor was it its design to, alter the existing private laws of the state further than was necessary to preserve consistency between the public and the private law. The Constitution is in fact the great stature of each State; an essential part of its private law, and nearly the whole if its public law. It is the supreme law, but not the fundamental law, in the sense of fons publici privatique juris. Its enactment produced less change in the laws of a State, than Magna Charta did in the Common Law. Apart from political considerations. The questions reserved for the exclusive cognizance of the courts of the United States were all within the competency, and might have been left to the decision, of the State courts. But the distinction between exclusive and concurrent jurisdiction was made, and the cases falling under either had may be ascertained, as has been already suggested, by reference to the ends and means of accomplishing them. The direct influence of the Constitution, as a public statute, upon the laws of the several States, has been much less than its indirect. The Common Law was recognized as the law of the land, but modified to suit the circumstances of the people of the Colonies. The courts, however, untrammelled by local and customary rules, which were venerable only for their antiquity, or which by prescription had become property, were at liberty, and often were compelled, to reinvestigate questions already decided in England, and for the proposes of inquiry to resort to foreign laws, universal reason, and colonial utility. Many, perhaps most, of the more eminent lawyers of the Colonies, down to the Revolution, were educated in England, and no doubt studied the Common Law, with the improvements which Lord Mansfield was then introducing. "It may be observed," says Chancellor Kent," and with greater width of truth of this country than of England, that a very large proportion of the matter contained in the old reporters prior to the English Revolution has been superseded, and is now cast into the shade by the improvements of modern times; by the cultivation of maritime jurisdiction; by the growing value and variety of personal property; by the spirit of commerce, and the enlargement of equity jurisdiction; by the introduction of more liberal and enlightened views of public policy, and, in short, by the study and influence of the Civil Law." The same causes, which were thus both in England and in the Colonies producing great alterations in the Common Law, received new energy and impetus from the Constitution. The law of the Colonies already conformed to a much greater extent than that of England to the jus gentium. Now, as has been seen, the principle of the Common Law which attributes jurisdiction to property, and denies it to those who are not landlords, renders the state a close corporation. In England the principle had been so modified as to attribute a share of jurisdiction to every native, but the alien, although encouraged to visit the kingdom for the purposes of commerce, found so many difficulties in the way of obtaining the privilege of citizenship, that he rarely asked for it. Their total exclusion practically preserved something of the spirit of municipalism in the law, the state was still a corporation. The right of membership could be obtained only with difficulty, and generally only on public considerations. But the Colonists had so little of the pride of citizenship in them, that they regarded England as their home, and America as a sort of decent asylum for the poor. Emigration was universally encouraged, and lands granted without any previous probation. The Constitution accorded with the sentiments of the people; it did not declare what should constitute citizenship, it did not limit Congress in its power to enact naturalization laws. Hence we have naturalized citizens who have become such as individuals, after a probation of five years supposed to be passed in learning to love and admire our institutions, and we have naturalized citizens who have become such as nations, having for our laws and institutions only such love as is felt by the conquered for the conqueror. When Congress, therefore, limited the probationary period to ten, seven, or five years, a mere point of time in the life of a nation, and also made citizenship depend entirely upon the pleasure of the alien to take it, citizenship ceased to be a privilege. This, with many other proximate causes, but all ultimately referable to the severance of jurisdiction from property, has carried the public and private law onward towards the entire abandonment of municipalism. The political consequences of the extension of citizenship to all who will become inhabitants of these States, are not within our consideration. But history is not silent, and furnishes thoughts which deserve to be meditated upon. In addition to these external and political causes of change in the Common Law, there are others of an internal nature. Its history presents to that of the Civil Law this contrast, that the Common Law is confined to the Anglo-Norman race. Whilst they spread their dominion over the face of the earth, they do not spread their municipal law. It is not the ardent desire of any of their conquered subjects to be governed by it. Their own people, as colonists, reject it. The inherent defect is its want of the power of self-defence. Its municipalism is merely conservatism, and has no element of progress, and without their union nothing moral can be permanent. Self-defence includes the power to be offensive, to destroy the purpose of self-preservation. But this is not the case with the Common Law of England. It is modified by contract with other laws, but never has impressed upon any of them its peculiarities. Now this does not arise from any narrowness of the principles of the law of property, for these are not more English than Roman or French. But from the perpetuation of the principle, that to property alone belongs jurisdiction, its political law. So, in the like manner, all that was peculiar to Rome expired with the fall of the Republic, and that which was common to humanity, the law of nature, was perpetuated. Another cause is, that the Common Law is eminently technical. In no other known system have formulas so powerful an effect. Fictions of the law are all equitable, and approve themselves to our natural reason; formulas are unmeaning except to those who have attained to "an artificial perfection of reason, gotten by lang study, and observation, and experience." Thus, that an estate granted to a person with the word heirs annexed should create in him an absolute inheritance, has no foundation in natural reason. Nor does this formula admit of accurate translation into the common language of literature, Latin. The proof of this is given by Bracton: after stating a limitation to A, and haeredibus sui corporis, he informs us that they take by descent "quamvis quibusdam videatur quod ipsi feoffati fuerint cum parentibus; quod non est verum." The reason of this opinion that he condemns is plain. Those who thought that the heirs of the body took joint interests with their parent gave the same meaning to these words, haeredibus sui corporis, that civilians give to sui haeredes. The latter mean children, lineal descendants, and so heirs of the body naturaliter, and used in that sense the children would take joint interests with their parents, as was decided in Wild's case. The error was in not perceiving that the limitation was a formula having a very different meaning from that which the words convey according to their idiomatic use. So the difference between the formula of a person dying leaving no issue, and leaving no issue living at the time of his death, is untranslatable, and even to the well-educated scholar of Continental Europe unintelligible. It is manifest that formulas do not commend themselves to the natural reason of mankind, and therefore cannot become the property of humanity. they are the mere husks of the law. But as the peculiarities of the Common Law of real estate are formulas, they too are destined to continue exceptional, if they do not disappear even from that system. CHAPTER XXX CONCLUSION The analysis of the fundamental principles of the Common Law has been made. It has been shown that our system is not "a shapeless mass of materials," as has been supposed by very eminent European jurists; and that there is a principle pervading in uniting together all parts of society, and controlling the state and the family, the beginning and the end of humanity; that the same bond which unites many in society unites two in marriage; that in whatever light we view these, the chief relations of human existence, comprehending omnes omuium charitates, it may be said with the utmost truth and accuracy, both of society and of marriage, that each is omnis vitae consortium, divini humanique juris communicatio. Our exposition has traced the rules of the law of real estate to the mixed law of the Middle Ages. Occasion has also been taken to exhibit some of the more important analogies between the Common and Civil Law, and to indicate the particular instances in which courts of justice and law writers were obliged to adopt such rules of the latter as were not inconsistent with the political principles of the former. The affinities of the two systems would perhaps justify a more extended examination, but it is sufficient to say that it is a matter of well-founded surprise that the Common Law judges have so frequently resorted to the Civil, and that it has been tolerated to so great a degree. For the hostility to the introduction of the Civil as the corpus juris of England was most natural and proper, and the attempt by the clergy exhibited, not only their ambition, but their ignorance of the Civil Law and the then existing condition of political affairs. As the Normans had no law suited to their condition at the time of their invasion of France, they readily adopted the mixed law. But it was far different three hundred years afterwards, when a portion of them, having established laws and well-ordered government, took possession of England. then they had a code suited to their new relations, and therefore with ancestral pride adhered to it. The change that was desirable, and that which they attempted, was to reconcile their conquered subjects to the feudal law which they themselves could not abandon without ruin. Only the slow progress of time could extinguish the hatred of the Saxon to the Norman. But the latter had no national antagonism to the Civil Law; on the contrary, their Continental brethren received it, as their predecessors had done, as a subsidiary law to explain and interpret the mixed law. And so thoroughly were the Normans changed in their manners, laws, and language by their conquest of Normandy, that they "were regarded both by Saxons and Danes as not only a different nation, but actually a different race. The historians of Denmark speak of the Norman conquerors of England as a people of Roman of Latin race, and deplore the conquest as a triumph of the roman blood over the Teutonic." All the tribes that acquired permanent settlements were alike transformed, and adopted the Civil Law, in the northern part of France as subsidiary, and in the southern part as the lex scripta. The conduct of the clergy, therefore, could lead only to failure. Their ignorance of the true spirit of the Civil Law was equally manifest. No nation that has ever existed, no code that has ever been contrived, are so tolerant of national customs. The Pandects will furnish a multitude of passages in which it is enjoined upon provincial rulers to respect local customs, and to maintain them with their authority, unless political interests demanded their abrogation. It was upon this very ground that the Northern barbarians so readily adopted it. The alternative view was not presented to them, to abandon their own customs and accept the Roman laws. It was in a similar spirit that the Conqueror agreed to tolerate the Saxon laws whilst he enforced his own code. When, therefore, the barons rejected the proposition of the clergy to abandon their native customs, they responded not only in the language, but in the spirit, of the Pandects. At the same time, our juridical history shows that courts and writers daily and openly appealed to that code to aid them in the interpretation of their laws. Finally, I have endeavored to show that our system of jurisprudence consists of many subordinate parts, all of which are connected by beautiful dependencies, and each of them, as I have fully persuaded myself, is reducible to a few plain elements, that will commend themselves to our natural reason, or be justified by the history and situation of our political ancestors. But if the law be merely an unconnected series of decisions and statutes, its use may remain, though its dignity as a science be lost. Reason must yield its supremacy to memory, and the cantor formularum is the greatest of lawyers. THE END