Osborne’s Criticism of the Argument from Existence

 

 

 

 

Background

 

In October 2001, I published a formal presentation of my “argument from the fact of existence,” and to date I have seen few attempts to refute it. The most serious attempt that I know of is Philip Osborne’s Ayn Rand’s Atheological Argument, which was published in 2002. Since its publishing, numerous readers of my website have written to inquire whether I had seen Osborne’s rejoinder to my argument (which I affectionately call “AFE”), and if I had any reaction of my own to publish in response to Osborne. I had, in fact, seen Osborne’s paper early on (probably not long after it was published), examined it, and even wrote several pages of notes which I had intended to edit down and finally publish on my own site. However, due to the usual time constraints, bigger priorities and even laziness, I never did finish my reply to Osborne’s rebuttal.

 

Recently a Christian reader of my website contacted me, and again I was asked whether I had a response to Osborne. With a heavy sigh, I originally intended to brush it off and promise that it’ll be up there “one day.” But this time I chose instead to make good on what I had promised myself well before this: to produce a thorough response to Osborne’s rebuttal of my AFE and publish it on my website. So I changed all my plans for the evening and sat down and peeled through Osborne’s paper completely afresh, not referring back to my earlier notes, and sculpted a thorough reply in one sitting. This I sent to my inquiring visitor who later said he “believe[s he] did read it,” but that he “may have accidentally deleted it” when I asked for his thoughts about it. I suppose even atheologists have to lump occasional ingratitude these days. Nonetheless, what I present below is an edited version of what I sent to my inquiring visitor.

 

Osborne’s paper actually rebuts two arguments that I have published on my website. Taking only one of my arguments to task would have been compliment enough. In addition to AFE, Osborne also interacts with an argument that I presented in my Letters to a Young Atheologist series, specifically Letter 6: God and Pure Self-Reference. While I think Osborne’s attempts to refute both arguments fail, I will only examine his interaction with AFE in the present paper. Should time avail itself, I’ll be happy to publish at a later time my response to the points Osborne raises against the argument from pure self-reference (which Osborne dubs “the argument from consciousness”).

 

 

 

 

Osborne on the Argument from the Fact of Existence

 


Among the more obvious points to make in response to Osborne's paper, I would first note that he's not actually interacting with my argument, even though he cites my presentation of it as a primary source. The argument he throws up before himself is the following:

 

1. If God exists, then the primacy of consciousness is true.

2. It is not the case that the primacy of consciousness is true.

3. Hence, it is not the case that God exists. (Modus tollens, from 1, 2)

 

Contrast this with the argument I present on my site:

 

Premise 1: If the primacy of consciousness is invalid, then the claim that God exists is false.

Premise 2: The primacy of consciousness is invalid.

Conclusion: Therefore, the claim that God exists is false.

 

This is a significant difference, one which Osborne apparently misses. Where the argument with which Osborne interacts concerns whether or not “God” exists, my argument shows why the knowledge claim that “God exists” cannot be accepted as true, principally because it assumes an invalid metaphysical basis – namely the primacy of consciousness view of reality. While no one has an onus to prove that the non-existent does not exist, one can show that claims such as “God exists” are false on account of the fact that they assume a false metaphysics. It is this latter approach that my argument takes. Claims that God exists thus fail to warrant the rationality needed to take them seriously.

 

Since the argument which I present is formally valid, there are basically two ways to attack it. One way is to challenge the first premise, arguing that the claim that God exists can still be true even if the primacy of consciousness is invalid. The other way is to deny the premise that the primacy of consciousness is invalid. The approach which Osborne chooses in his rebuttal is more in line with the former than with the latter, essentially arguing that the primacy of existence does not rule out the notion that a god exists. Along the way, however, Osborne makes numerous minor errors which collectively impact his understanding of the argument from existence even more negatively. For instance, Osborne says that

 

the central idea of the Objectivist atheological argument is the dichotomy between the “primacy of existence” and the “primacy of consciousness.”

 

The central idea behind AFE is not simply that the primacy of consciousness and the primacy of existence are opposed to one another, but that the idea of God presumes the primacy of consciousness and that the primacy of consciousness is metaphysically invalid. The central idea, in other words, is that god-belief is false because it philosophically rests on a false metaphysics. I have provided ample support for the premise that god-belief assumes the metaphysical primacy of consciousness in my presentation of AFE. And – and this is important – even though Osborne’s rebuttal seeks to deny that the notion of God assumes the primacy of consciousness, he does not raise any challenge to the exhibits that I produce in defense of this premise.

 

It is important to point out here that, in any scrutable case, a knowledge claim performatively presumes the opposite principle, namely the primacy of existence principle – even those knowledge claims which are false, mistaken or even arbitrary, and even if the speaker does not fully understand this. This is because, when one makes a serious pronouncement about the world, he does not, for instance, assume that his claim is true simply because he wishes that it’s true. Nor does he typically suppose that things would be different if he wanted them to change. As I point out in Note 2.I.B.1.:

 

The distinction between the things that exist and the faculty of perceiving that which exists is the basis of the concept 'objectivity' and gives rise to the objective, hierarchical nature of knowledge. That we can identify the fact that knowledge is hierarchical in nature confirms the far-reaching relevance of the distinction between existence and consciousness.

 

If I were writing my argument today, however, I would elaborate on the fundamental necessity of the primacy of existence principle in knowledge in Premise 2.II. However, readers should note that, in Note 2.I.C.1., I do point the reader to another article of mine, The Issue of Metaphysical Primacy, which deals more directly with this relationship. I would also point out that an attempt to affirm the opposite – namely the position that knowledge assumes the primacy of consciousness – amounts to affirming a position philosophically akin to the view that “wishing makes it true.” Not even most theists will explicitly affirm that wishing makes it true, and yet in terms of essentials this is the ultimate foundational premise of their worldview – that reality conforms to some conscious activity, such as wishing (e.g., the Christian god wished the universe into existence). All this is to say that there’s more at stake, according to the fundamental principles informing AFE, than merely siding on one or the other horn of a dichotomy. In fact, the issue is whether one’s claims have their basis in reality (the primacy of existence), or in fantasy (the primacy of consciousness).

 

Osborne interprets the primacy of existence to mean:

 

“’existence’ (which I will take to mean the actual world, which I will call ‘@’) holds ‘primacy’ (is ontologically independant of) consciousness.”

 

It’s important at this point to keep in mind that consciousness also exists, that it is part of the actual world; it is just as real as rivers, photosynthesis and digestion. This point, which is unmistakably affirmed in the Objectivist literature, is often ignored or misunderstood by Objectivism’s detractors. I’m not accusing Osborne of doing this, but if he is not careful, he very well may fall prey to this common error. The concern here is that we should not dichotomize existence and consciousness against one another, as if they were two opposites which cannot be integrated or must be reconciled due to intervening differences. Consciousness is an attribute belonging to a specific class of entities, namely living organisms (specifically those living organisms which have evolved a faculty of awareness). The issue which Rand raises in considering metaphysical primacy, is the proper relationship between consciousness and existence, or, more specifically, because a conscious subject and the objects of its awareness. So while we may speak of the primacy of existence and the primacy of consciousness as being at odds with one another, it would be wrong to speak of existence and consciousness as being at odds with each other. Since the primacy of existence is the proper relationship between a subject and its objects, Objectivism promotes a profound harmoniousness between consciousness and existence.

 

Osborne’s approach to critiquing his rendition of the argument is to grant the assumption that the primacy of existence and the primacy of consciousness are jointly exhaustive metaphysics (in Note 2.I.B.3. I link to this article which defends this position), as well as the assumption that the primacy of existence is true. He believes that he can dispel the argument by showing that God does not assume or imply the primacy of consciousness metaphysics, that God is compatible with the primacy of existence metaphysics. Thus he wants to attack his rendition’s first premise, namely:

 

If God exists, then the primacy of consciousness is true.

 

To follow this approach, he states that

 

“part of the problem in understanding it is that it is difficult to understand what sense of ‘dependance’ the Objectivist means when he says that theism supposes @ to be ‘dependant’ upon God.”

 

It is not clear, however, why this would be difficult for anyone who has examined my argument to grasp. In fact, it seems that anyone familiar with my presentation of AFE would have to deliberately ignore examples which I give in defense of the premise that the idea of God assumes or reduces to the primacy of consciousness in order to take the approach Osborne is about to deploy. For instance, in Premise 1.II.B.2.b., I list three examples of what I mean by this:

 

i.               God is said to have created the universe (i.e., existence) through an act of will.

ii.              God can change A into non-A (i.e., alter the identity of entities) through an act of will.

iii.             God can make A perform the action of non-A (i.e., alter the causal nature of entities) through an act of will.

 

So we have three species of dependence of @ on a form of consciousness, namely creation of existence by an act of will (e.g., “wishing” things into reality), changing an object into something it’s not by an act of will (e.g., “commanding” water to become wine), making an object perform the action of something it is not by an act of will (e.g., enabling men to walk on water, or fish and loaves of bread to magically multiply). But curiously, in his critique, Osborne ignores my point that “a will is a form of consciousness” (Premise 1.II.B.2.b.vi.) and examines the argument from the erroneous assumption that consciousness is restricted exclusively to perception alone. He makes this clear when he tries to sort out the “difficulty” he mentions above with the following interpretation:

 

It seems plausible to me that he means it is perceptually dependant.

 

Nowhere in my version of the argument do I define the primacy of consciousness to mean merely “perceptually dependant.” To correct this, I can spell it out quite easily: the primacy of consciousness holds that existence (specifically, the objects of consciousness) depends in one way or another on some form or activity of consciousness (such as a will, which I specifically mention in my own examples) for their existence, identity, activity, ability, etc. I don’t want to accuse Osborne of sleight of hand, but if his critique is guilty of it, it’s most guilty of it on this point.

 

He explains what he means by “perceptually dependant” as follows:

 

For instance, one might say that reality is constituted by our perception of it; for example, this essay comes into existence when you start reading it, and no longer exists when you stop, because it is a product of your mind. This seems consistent with Objectivist statements, regarding the primacy of consciousness:

 

It may be consistent with what Objectivism states about the primacy of consciousness (for perception is a form of consciousness, among other things), but it is not exhaustive of the manner in which this fundamental error can be committed. Other instances would also constitute expressions of the primacy of consciousness, such as:

 

a) This essay comes into existence when:

·       You start to think about it

·       You hope it exists

·       You fear that it exists

·       You wish that it exists

·       You command it to exist

·       You believe it exists, etc.

 

b) This essay goes out of existence if

·       You think it should

·       You hope it does

·       You’re afraid it will

·       You believe it will

·       You want it to

·       You deny its existence, etc.

 

c) This essay says something other than it does say because

·       You want it to say something else

·       You want others to believe it says something else

·       You imagine it says something else

·       You pretend it says something else

·       You believe it says something else

·       You forgot what it really says, etc.

 

In each case, we have a form or activity of consciousness other than perception which is given primacy over its objects. It would constitute a failure of cognition to suppose that “perceptual dependence” constitutes the primacy of consciousness while maintaining that these other examples do not. In terms of fundamentals, all these examples are species of the same reversal of the relationship between consciousness and its objects, which means: all are expressions of the same basic error.

 

So Osborne’s critique seeks to undermine the argument by arbitrarily restricting consciousness merely to perception, thus ignoring expressions of the primacy of consciousness which incorporate other forms or activities of consciousness, even those specified in my version of the argument he’s trying to critique. To the degree that his rebuttal does this, it mischaracterizes AFE.

 

To support his construal of the primacy of consciousness as being restricted merely to an issue of “perceptual dependence,” Osborne quotes two passages from my essay The Issue of Metaphysical Primacy. But neither of these statements, nor any other statements in that or any other essay that I have written, affirms that perception is the only form or activity of consciousness. But this is what he would need if he was going to substantiate the construal of the primacy of consciousness which his critique’s approach utilizes as a viable criticism of AFE. He also paraphrases Rand herself in an attempt to justify his construal, namely:

 

Consciousness is the faculty which perceives that which exists.

 

But this statement, too, in no way restricts consciousness to perception and only perception. Consciousness is indeed the faculty which perceives that which exists, but it is also the faculty which performs other operations, such as differentiating objects, selectively focusing on one or a group of objects in the midst of many, omitting measurements, forming basic concepts and higher abstractions, inferring, remembering, emoting, daydreaming, pondering, wishing, fantasizing, etc. Rand makes this explicitly clear in her essay “For the New Intellectual” (in her book of the same title, cf. pp. 14-15) where she points out that human beings share their consciousness with animals at the levels of sensations and perceptions, but are capable of much beyond these that animals are not capable of (she focused mainly on man’s conceptual ability). What we find in Osborne’s critique of Objectivist atheology, then, is that it relies heavily on the fallacy which Rand herself called frozen abstraction. This fallacy occurs when a particular unit substitutes for the wider class to which it belongs. In this case, Osborne substitutes perception, which is one species of consciousness, for the wider class of consciousness itself, as if these other aspects – e.g., forming concepts, inferring, remembering, emoting, wishing, etc. – did not belong to the same class. But they do belong to the same class. Why suppose that perception is a conscious ability, but thinking, wanting, imagining, remembering, inferring, and emoting are not? Osborne gives no good reason for abandoning these latter species of consciousness from the concept ‘consciousness’. And yet this is precisely what his rebuttal to AFE does.

 

So Osborne is wrong to say:

 

This seems to be what Objectivists mean when they say that God-belief violates fundamental axioms; the only relation which consciousness can enter into with reality is one of perception...

 

Perception per se is not a “relation... with reality”; rather it is an activity of an organism which possesses at least the perceptual level of consciousness. To correct Osborne, Objectivism holds that the only relation which consciousness can enter into with reality is that identified by the primacy of existence: the objects of consciousness hold metaphysical primacy over the subject of consciousness (hence “Objectivism”). Anyone can recognize the truth in this by isolating various activities of consciousness and checking whether or not the objects involved in those activities conform to those activities. Does your perception of a lemon cause it to exist or be a lemon as opposed to something else (like a mushroom or automobile)? Obviously not. Does your wish that your electric bill for a month in the deep cold of winter stay below $100.00 make it stay below $100.00? No – you can wish all you want, but you still owe $180.00 all the same. Does thinking that it’s really March and not November make it March? No, it doesn’t. Does longing for a long lost friend restore the years you didn’t enjoy with him? No, those years when he was present in your life are gone, and they will not change because you longed for him. Etc. Reality is what it is, regardless of what we think, feel, wish or prefer to be the case. That’s essentially what the primacy of existence principle is recognizing. Religion, however, enshrines an imaginary being which is supposedly not bound to this orientation between subject and object, but allegedly enjoys its reversal – that the objects of its consciousness conform to what it thinks, feels, wishes, or prefers to be the case. Thus religion assumes the primacy of consciousness metaphysics.

 

Osborne’s attempts to interpret the primacy of existence through the filter of analytic philosophy, however, has a strong potential to confuse matters, especially since he proceeds on the erroneous basis that the Objectivist conception of consciousness is restricted merely to perception. He thus presents the primacy of existence as he understands it in the form of a symbolic proposition:

 

For all x, if x is a member of @, then for any property F which x has, x has F whether or not any individual y enters into relation R with x.

 

Osborne stipulates that R “denote[s] a perceptual relationship,” such that “Rxy is true just in case x perceives y.” Though this is not entirely clear, I interpret the above statement to say something along the lines of:

 

For any thing, if that thing is a member of the world of things (i.e., if it exists), then for any property that this thing has, this thing has that property whether or not any conscious individual perceives that thing.


Let’s plug a concrete object in for “x” and see if it bears out.

 

For any lemon, if that lemon is a member of the world of things (i.e., if it exists), then the fact that it has mass is a property of that lemon whether I perceive that lemon or not.

 

So for any lemon which actually exists, why would I suppose that it does not have mass if I do not perceive it? Similarly, however, why would I suppose that it does not have mass if I wished that it did not have mass? Or, why would I suppose that any particular lemon does not have mass if I am not aware that it exists? Indeed, I acknowledge the primacy of existence, so I recognize that lemons are what they are independent of any activity of my consciousness, whether it be merely perceiving, or knowing, thinking, feeling, wishing, denying, evading, ignoring, forgetting, preferring, etc. Given his construal of the primacy of existence, however, Osborne would have it that this relationship obtains only in the case of perception.

 

In response to this propositional formulation which Osborne concocts, he says that he “will take the truth of this proposition to be a sufficient condition for the truth of primacy of existence metaphysics.” This reading constitutes a reversal which we can expect an advocate of analytic philosophy to endorse in uncritical haste. Propositions (regardless of their truth value) are not a sufficient condition for proper orientation between a consciousness and its objects; quite the opposite is the case: the proper orientation between a consciousness and its objects is a necessary condition for forming any propositions to begin with, as well as for informing our identifications of reality truthfully. Propositions, it should be remembered, are not irreducible; they consist of concepts, and concepts are formed by a conscious process (namely concept-formation). Propositions are the product of enormous integrations performed by a consciousness that is capable of forming concepts from what it perceives in the world. Also, since truth is the error-free identification of facts of reality, and identification of anything in reality is possible for a consciousness only if it is first aware of what it seeks to identify, the primacy of existence is a minimum precondition for such exercises. So Osborne unwittingly demonstrates the implicit commitment of analytical philosophy to the primacy of consciousness without realizing it by promulgating such a blatant reversal.

 

Osborne suggests agreement with the primacy of existence principle (his abbreviated version of it anyway) when he states

 

It seems consistent with the intuition that objects bear their characteristics independently of the fact of whether or not any being exists to perceive them.

 

It should be noted that, however “intuition” is construed, it is typically understood to constitute an operation of consciousness, so the act of “intuiting” this truth would involve not only consciousness but also some object(s) which it considers (such as the statement “existence exists independent of consciousness”) and thus serves to exemplify an instance of the truth it seeks to interpret. In other words, it would be self-refuting to "intuit" otherwise.

 

It is at this point, however, that Osborne reaffirms his arbitrary restriction of Objectivism’s conception of consciousness to merely perception. (I call his restriction arbitrary because Osborne gives no reason why “perceptual dependence” would qualify as an instance of the primacy of consciousness, but not, say, wishful dependence, that is, dependence on wishing.) He states:

 

Recall earlier the axiom of consciousness, which states that the only relation which consciousness can enter into with any other member of @ must be of a kind R.

 

In other words, he is saying that the axiom of consciousness holds that “the only relation which consciousness can enter into with any [thing that exists] must be [perceptual in nature].” But as we saw above, the axiom of consciousness nowhere restricts its own scope of reference in this manner at all. Is it not by means of consciousness that I consider the fax that I received at work today – and left at my office? I’m not perceiving it now – I’m recalling it, the very action of consciousness which Osborne asks his reader to use when he re-emphasizes his arbitrary construal of the axiom of consciousness! Osborne makes use of many operations of consciousness other than perception, but apparently fails to realize that they are operations of consciousness.

 

He then reinterprets the argument from existence on this misconstrued basis:

 

Thus, if God's consciousness is to be metaphysically active, in the sense of being able to create objects, it must do so by entering into an R-relation with @. But this violates Proposition A. Hence, God-belief advocates the primacy of consciousness. It follows that if the primacy of consciousness is false, then God does not exist.

 

In other words, the notion “God” can only be thought to assume the primacy of consciousness if it is held that existence of objects (e.g., the universe, etc.) depends on its perception of those objects. This leaves completely open all the other expressions of the primacy of consciousness which Objectivism identifies and which I have specified in my argument. Since the primacy of consciousness has been construed to encompass only “perceptual dependence,” the notion that the earth depends on someone’s wishing, for instance, could not be categorized as an expression of the primacy of consciousness, even though in terms of essentials it reduces to the same orientation between subject and object entailed by “perceptual dependence.” How far Osborne has wandered off from what the original argument from existence argues!

 

Osborne then says that the argument is unsound because:

 

There seems to be no argument to demonstrate that it is conceptually impossible for any form of consciousness to enter into relations with @ that are not of a kind R.

 

He chalks this oversight up to the axiom of consciousness, and yet the axiom of consciousness – as I showed above – nowhere claims that perception is the only form or activity of consciousness. Indeed, where did Osborne get the notion “conceptually possible”? Conceptual thought is a form of conscious activity, and Objectivism includes this type of activity within the range of units denoted by the axiom of consciousness. It also includes other types of conscious activity, such as emotion, wishing, inferring, reminiscing, etc.

 

So whether he realizes it or not, Osborne has ineluctably attacked a straw man – a complete mischaracterization of the argument from existence that I have presented. He does this primarily by arbitrarily restricting the axiom of consciousness to mean only perceptual awareness, and not allowing it to include other forms and activities of consciousness, and then recasting the primacy of consciousness on this erroneous basis. Since, on Osborne's view, forms or activities of consciousness other than perception are exempt from partaking in the error that is the primacy of consciousness, the argument from existence (on this reading) cannot soundly draw the conclusion that the statement "God exists" is false.

 

Resting on this, Osborne then quotes Scott Ryan (from his Objectivism and the Corruption of Rationality):

 

The axiom that "existence exists," to the extent that it means anything at all, is apparently intended to affirm what John Searle has called "external realism". Such realism, as we saw in the preceding chapter, he characterizes as "the view that there is a way things are that is logically independent of all human representations" [The Construction of Social Reality, p. 155]. But as Searle is at pains to argue, such realism does not, in and of itself, entail that physical reality is causally independent of consciousness.

 

Ryan is conflating the axiom of existence with the primacy of existence. The axiom of existence simply affirms the fact that there is a reality as a fundamental and irreducible primary. By itself, it makes no explicit statement about the relationship between consciousness and its objects. Only when we get to the axiom of consciousness (which is inevitable) does the relationship between consciousness and its objects (and with this the distinction between internal and external phenomena) become an issue. This is the issue of metaphysical primacy, and it is here where we discover and identify the proper relationship between consciousness and its objects. It is important to recognize, as pointed out above, that, according to Objectivism, the concept ‘existence’ includes everything and anything which exists, including consciousness. The notion ‘external realism’ suggests that everything 'outside of' or "external to" consciousness is real, and thus hazards the implication that consciousness itself is not, or at least the inner workings of consciousness are not real (though at points in his writings Searle seems to avoid this). The problem here is that the descriptor “external” may be affirmed without contextual understanding of the subject-object relationship, thus inviting the offending implication. Objectivism – and thereby the axioms – rejects this kind of implication by virtue of its recognition that consciousness also exists.

 

Now many critics of Objectivism seek to make a lot of hay from vague, isolated resemblances between some of its affirmations and expressions and those found in other philosophies, and the resulting association is exploited so as to tarnish our impression of it in some way. Ryan, who is notorious for (apparently deliberately) misrepresenting what Objectivism teaches (see for instance this review of his aforementioned criticism of Objectivism), finds his equation of the axiom of existence with Searle’s “external realism” all too convenient as he tries to import Searle’s confessions and admissions into Objectivism. This doesn’t work; the primacy of existence explicitly identifies the proper relationship between consciousness and its objects, while Searle’s thesis leaves this matter shrouded in murkiness. So while Searle’s “external realism” might “not, in and of itself, entail that physical reality is causally independent of consciousness,” the primacy of existence tells us that physical objects do in fact exist independent of consciousness. That is the essence of the recognition which the primacy of existence denotes: that existence exists independent of consciousness. Meanwhile those who want to claim that “physical reality” causally depends on consciousness, are invited to demonstrate this.

 

But insofar as Searle’s position is concerned, Ryan’s point can be taken seriously. For one can, assuming Searle’s point of view, affirm that, on the one hand “there is a way things are that is logically independent of all human representations,” and yet, on the other, also affirm that “physical reality” is causally dependent on consciousness. For instance, we use the name 'Mt. McKinley' to refer to or "represent" a particular mountain in Alaska. So the name “Mt. McKinley” is literally a human representation of something that exists in a particular way. Obviously the mountain to which this name refers exists independent of the name (the “human representation”) which we use to designate it. But this does not, as Ryan points out, rule out the thesis that the mountain designated by the name “Mt. McKinley” is “causally dependent” on consciousness – as if a conscious action (such as wishing or commanding) put it there. If one fails to recognize the primacy of existence, he could say on the one hand that Mt. McKinley is “logically independent” of any “human representation” which we apply to it (after all, we would not expect all languages to accommodate the name “Mt. McKinley”), while still maintaining that a supernatural consciousness brought it into being. This is because, on Searle’s view, his “external realism” does not isolate the proper relationship between consciousness and its objects. Indeed, it is because Searle is not armed with the primacy of existence principle that his position can easily succumb to the metaphysical subjectivism that results from the reversal of that relationship. Rather than bringing viable criticism against Objectivism, Ryan simply manages to demonstrate what can happen without it.

 

It should be pointed out here that, by simply raising this concern, Ryan inadvertently confirms AFE’s appropriateness in focusing on theism’s dependence on the primacy of consciousness. He makes this clear by virtue of the fact that, as a theist, he wants to keep the idea that “physical reality” is causally dependent on consciousness philosophically available. Otherwise, why would he raise this point?

 

Osborne then curiously states (having bought into his own faulty construal):

 

This proposal is consistent with the primacy of existence so long as we suppose such causal relations are not perceptual relations.

 

What he is really saying is that the primacy of existence is compatible with expressions of the primacy of consciousness which hoist forms of consciousness other than perceptual awareness above any object(s) one might choose to indicate. Consequently, wishing can hold metaphysical primacy over the objects of consciousness, as can thinking, preferring, desiring, imagining, evading, etc. Only by arbitrarily restricting consciousness as the argument from existence understands it exclusively to perception, can Osborne claim to have inoculated theism against AFE. Were the argument already ineffective on its own terms, critics would not need to take such dubious measures.

 

Even more curiously, Osborne says that “such things as telepathy and telekinesis do not seem to violate the primacy of consciousness, even though they involve mental actions.” I would love for Osborne to demonstrate these abilities which he cites. If he could, I’m sure he would not need to spend his time developing counter-arguments against essays on atheology. All he would need to do is demonstrate these abilities and that would effectively demonstrate the reality of the primacy of consciousness metaphysics.

 

 

Conclusion

 

Osborne has failed to refute the argument from existence. His chosen path was not to argue that the primacy of consciousness is true, or that views premised on the primacy of consciousness can actually be compatible with the primacy of existence. Rather, the intent here was to show that the idea of God does not actually assume the primacy of consciousness, and therefore does not violate the primacy of existence. To do this, he had to restrict the axiom of consciousness to entail exclusively perception – a stipulation that is fundamentally contrary to what Objectivism teaches, thus allowing other forms of consciousness to enjoy free reign over its objects (cf. telepathy and telekinesis). So Osborne’s criticism of the argument from existence commits the fallacy known as frozen abstraction. As I make clear above as well as in my presentation of the argument from existence, consciousness involves more than merely perception, and the axiom of consciousness includes every form and activity of consciousness that we have discovered and will discover (just as the concept ‘man’ includes every man who exists now, who has existed and will exist). If we recognize that the notion that an object depends on a subject’s perception of it constitutes an instance of the primacy of consciousness, why wouldn’t we also recognize that the notion that an object depends on a subject’s will or imagination or commandments also grants metaphysical primacy to consciousness? By use of a frozen abstraction in place of the axiom of consciousness, Osborne seeks to special plead his way out of the devastating conclusion of the argument from existence. But just as two wrongs don’t make a right, two fallacies don’t add up to a worthy refutation. If critics want to take down the argument from existence, they’ll have to keep trying.

 

 

Copyright 2007 Anton Thorn. All rights reserved.

 

[Back to Top]

[Back to Anton Thorn's Main Page]

[Back to the Argument from Existence]