In Defense of the Supererogatory & Suberogatory
In
a three-fold model of morality*,
acts are either obligatory, right (permissible), or wrong.
However, there are acts that seem permissible in the three-fold model
that do not fit intuitionally: the supererogatory and the suberogatory.
This paper will present the advantages of a moral theory that
accommodates these categories.
*
Frederick Carney explains an Islamic five-fold model that also includes the
recommended and the discouraged. For
the purpose of this paper, I am roughly equating them with the
supererogatory and the suberogatory. See
Carney, “Some Aspects of Islamic Ethics,” 1983.
**
Julia Driver, "The Suberogatory," Australasian Journal of
Philosophy, 70 (1992) p. 286-7.
Supererogatory acts are those that, according
to a three-fold model of morality, are permissible, but not obligatory.
Furthermore, these acts are seen as above and beyond the call of duty.
Acts of this type needn’t be heroic: opening a door for someone whose
arms are full of groceries could be considered a supererogatory act.
Suberogatory acts, then, are acts that are
permissible; not wrong. These acts
typically cause a level of moral criticism or uneasiness, but are not so morally
amiss that they are forbidden.
Consider the following case:
“in boarding a train the person who is first gets first choice of
seats. But suppose that the train
is almost full, and a couple wish to sit together, and there is only one place
where there are two seats together. If
the person ahead of them takes one of those seats, when he could have taken
another less convenient seat, and knowing that the two behind him wanted to sit
together, then he has done something blameworthy.
Yet, if he gives up this seat, and takes a less desirable
one, he has done something praiseworthy. The
problem is justifying the blame when the agent is acting within his rights.
The people who want to sit together have no claim against the person
ahead of them in line. Thus, he has
no obligation to pass up a more convenient seat.**”
(Driver, Suberogatory, 287)
Driver thus introduces the topic of
“morally charged situations:” situations in which the agent’s only options
are to either supererogate or suberogate. It
is precisely for these situations that a moral theory is advantaged for
accommodating the supererogatory and suberogatory.
When an agent is acting within her own
rights, such as in the above case, one is intuitionally hesitant to say that by
taking the more convenient seat, she is acting wrongly.
Consider the following additions to the case: Grumpy, the person before
the couple on the train, has had a long day.
He has worked hard, and is tired. His
only current thought is to board the train, and finally be able to rest.
The place where the couple can sit is much more convenient, perhaps even
with a view. Thus Grumpy takes the
seat, thankful that he can finally rest.
The
couple, on the other hand, while wishing to sit together, have the option of
moving once an additional place once someone has left (whether Grumpy or another
passenger). Of course, the case can
be further amended that the couple have also had a bad day, etc., however, the
status of the couple may not have any effect on Grumpy’s actions.
Similarly,
if Merna the mailwoman, while delivering her route, sees a child trapped in a
burning building, she is obligated to call for help.
Should she choose to risk her own life to save the child, she
supererogates. One wishes to say
she is praiseworthy for doing so. And
yet, according to the three-fold model of morality, while what she has done is
permissible, it is no more than that.
One can imagine the following criticism:
Supererogatory, nor suberogatory, acts exist.
Supererogatory acts are merely permissible, or possibly obligatory.
Suberogatory acts, on the other hand, are either merely permissible, or
simply wrong.
The response to this is two fold: (1) if
supererogatory acts are right or obligatory, does Merna have an obligation to
risk her own life? Certainly not.
Having an obligation to risk one’s life (as opposed to
calling for professionals to help), is counterintuitive.
Is it merely permissible, and thereby not praiseworthy?
One would hope not. Risking
one’s life for another, especially in the case where Merna does not have any
connection to the trapped child, should be a praiseworthy act.
(2) if suberogatory acts are either permissible or wrong, is Grumpy, by
virtue of permissible acts carrying neither praiseworthiness nor
blameworthiness, not blameworthy for taking a seat that is obviously wanted (and
arguably maximizes utility) by others? One
wishes to say that he is, even if only slightly.
Furthermore, if suberogatory acts are merely wrong, Grumpy performs a
wrong act by taking the seat, which is within his rights: he is the first to
board the train, and thus has his choice of seats.
A
moral theory which accommodates the supererogatory and suberogatory, therefore,
eases intuition significantly. It
better explains everyday life, much like the five-fold model.
Such examples as presented above occur every day, and are not at all
uncommon. To say that Merna either
has an obligation to risk her life, or that is she not praiseworthy for doing
so, seems counterintuitive, and indeed it is.
To say that Grumpy is either not blameworthy for breaking up a couple, or
that he has committed a forbidden act is also counterintuitive.
A moral theory that encompasses the categories of supererogatory and
suberogatory therefore accounts for these actions, better applying morality to
real life.