NIETZSCHE, GENEALOGY,
AND
THE CRITIQUE OF POWER *
Große Dinge verlangen daß man
von ihnen schweigt oder groß
redet: groß, das heißt, zynisch und
mit Unschuld. (WM § 1)
Introduction
It
would be an impossible task to introduce here the thought of a great
philosopher as Friedrich Nietzsche, as the subject-matter of his grand oeuvre resists the classifications and
operations of traditional hermeneutics. Even before Foucault sought to rescue a
"critique of power" in the Sache
of a Nietzschean semiology, Martin Heidegger had remarked, "'Nietzsche'
--der Name des Denkers steht als Titel für die
Sache seines Denkens."[1] The name
of the philosopher coincides, in this particular case, with the very
subject-matter of the philosophy in question. To assign a "critique of
power" to Nietzsche is, to say the least, a risky procedure. It would be
thus impossible to relate Nietzsche's thought to Kant's critical philosophy
without caricaturing the originality of the former or the systematic rigor of
the latter. As shown by many scholarly studies,[2] Kant and
Nietzsche have critical projects that radically differ --despite some points of
convergence-- not only in their philosophical formulations but in their very
presuppositions and concepts, especially in their views of morality and human
nature. In order to avoid the simplistic conclusion that Nietzsche did not
understand Kant, I decided to articulate Nietzsche's reading of Kant with the
former's philosophy as a whole, especially in its radical critique of modernity
and the modern conception of human nature (Menschlichkeit,
the humanum). Only in light of a
diagnosis of modern man, which Nietzsche undertakes in a
quasi-prophetic--albeit non-messianic-- manner, can we understand the true
meaning of his critical project, and its implications for our history and
culture. What is stake, therefore, is the recasting of what may be termed the
Nietzschean problematic of modern subjectivity, to wit, the question of the
self-overcoming (Selbstüberwindung)
of modern man, conjugated with correlative concepts such as the will to power (der Wille zur Macht) and the eternal
return (die ewige Wiederkehr),
elaborated in organic, interactive fashion, quasi methodically, within a
critical tradition to be overcome by philosophy itself. That the question of
human nature steals the scene, as it were, in the staging of a Nietzschean theatrum philosophicum does not demean
Kant's philosophy, insofar as the critical thrust of the latter is brought to
the foreground. Reminiscent of the tripartite division of Kant's
"cosmopolitan philosophy," Nietzsche outlined the second book of his unfinished,
controversial work on the Will to Power[3] (II.
Buch: Kritik der höchsten Werte):
1.
Kritik der Religion
2.
Kritik der Moral
3.
Kritik der Philosophie
Such
will be the thematic division that will underlie this chapter, as I will seek
to elaborate on Nietzsche's genealogical critique of power, starting from his
critique of Kant and leading to Foucault's reappropriation of the former. Like
Kant's, this threefold criticism is articulated by Nietzsche with a view to
rescuing a conception of human nature that avoids the metaphysical impasse of
reducing the humanum to a reflex of
the divinum, of a transcendens, at the same time as it
articulates the historical, immanent presuppositions proper to the human
species, qua animal to be distinguished from all the others, by its development
and history. If Kant had anticipated Hegel's philosophy of history, it is in
the historicizing of human nature that Nietzsche finds one point of
rapprochement, in the very conception of an effective historicity, implicit to
a genealogy that radicalizes what Hegel called the "science of human
experience" (Wissenschaft der
Erfahrung des Geistes).[4]
"παvτες
αvθρωπoι τoυ
ειδεvαι oρεγovται
φυσει. σημειov δ'η
τωv αισθησεωv
αγαπησις (...) All men, by nature, aim at
knowledge; a sign of this is [our] affection by the senses." The famous
words that open Aristotle's Metaphysics
(I,1 980a) indicated already the place of the empeiria in a classical conception of human nature qua rational
being: only the human species (τo γεvoς τωv
αvθρωπωv) has the faculty to order its experience
(εμπειρια), starting from the
sensations and memory, to acquire and develop art (τεχvη)
and science (επιστημη). When Nietzsche
develops the concept of the "will to know" two millenia later, it is
still this same human nature which is to be investigated, starting from
experience. Nietzsche's psychological inquiry into the nature of human
instincts and drives is indeed very reminiscent of the work undertaken by Kant
in the Anthropologie. To be sure, it
is Kant's refusal to remain on the empirical level of investigation that will
prompt Nietzsche's attack upon any future metaphysics of sorts. The question of
human nature, the nature in question, "man" as a perennial remise en question, has been a major
characteristic of philosophy since Heraclitus sought in thought what was common
to all human beings, since Protagoras held man to be the measure of all things,
and a fortiori since Socrates denied such measure, allowing for Plato and
Aristotle to corroborate the shift from a philosophizing on the nature (physis) of beings to a philosophizing of
their formal essence (ousia).It was
this teleological, and hence metaphysical, conception of human nature that came
under Nietzsche's attack, precisely because of its pretense to know the truth
of a human nature, once and for all established. In effect, for Nietzsche --as
it was for Heidegger--, the rise of Platonism coincides with the emergence of
metaphysics. Although it is beyond the scope of the present study to
recapitulate the development of different conceptions of human nature
throughout the centuries, it was by deconstructing the history of metaphysics
that Nietzsche himself set out to elaborate on a genealogical conception of
human nature, beyond good and evil. Therefore, it was in order to recast the
modern reformulation of a classical problematic such as "human
nature," understood in its Aristotelian correlation between rationality
and sociability,[5]
that I undertook a brief study of the critical background of Kant's conception
of human nature, in its self-constitution within a society of free subjects.
The present essay is confined to Nietzsche's "anthropology" and its
relation to the critique of metaphysics and morality, as I seek to highlight
the central place it occupies in his overall work and how it anticipates
Foucault's genealogy of modernity.
1. Critique and Genealogy: Of Truth and Method
Wahrheitssinn. Ich lobe mir eine jede
Skepsis, auf welche mir erlaubt ist zu antworten: "Versuchen wir's!"
Aber ich mag von allen Dingen und allen Fragen, welche das Experiment nicht
zulassen, nichts mehr hören. Dies ist die Grenze meines
"Wahrheitssinn": denn dort hat die Tapferkeit ihr Recht
verloren. (FW § 51)
What
is philosophy? How is philosophy to be opposed to nonphilosophy? This
problematic was announced, from the outset, as constitutive of the
methodological analysis that has opposed great thinkers such as Kant and
Nietzsche, Habermas and Foucault. As Mary Rawlinson has argued, Foucault's
conception of philosophy radically departs from a systematic, scientific
undertaking to apprehend reality, such as Kant's and Hegel's Wissenschaft or Husserl's Phänomelogie.(KPS 371) And yet Foucault
--just like Nietzsche-- did not seek to abandon philosophy to the obscure
caprices of unreason, but rather refused to have it confined to a purely
logical, dogmatic pattern of rationality, supposedly neutral, transcendental or
presuppositionless. That question also underlies Nietzsche's writings in its
different stages of evolution --grosso
modo, one may speak of three major phases: the early writings, marked by
philology, the artistic passion (in particular, music), and the friendship with
Wagner (e.g., Die Geburt der Tragödie,
1872, and the four Unzeitgemäße
Betrachtungen, 1873-76); the second, after the rupture with Wagner (1878),
marked by the disillusionment of reason (Menschliches,
Allzumenschliches, 1878-80, and Die
fröhliche Wissenschaft, 1882); and the third, marked by the masterpieces Also sprach Zarathustra (1883-84, 1885),
Jenseits von Gut und Böse (1886), Zur Genealogie der Moral (1887), Die Götzen-dämmerung (1889), and the Nachlaß, Der Antichrist (1895), Ecce
Homo (1908), Der Wille zur Macht
(1901,1906).[6]
In all these works, the question of philosophy is connected to other questions,
such as the problems of life, human existence, and truth. And in all these
central questions, the Nietzschean experimentalism emerges as the only
commonplace that points to a critical,textual pathway, an experimental method
of research, at once Experiment and Versuch, the genealogical perspectivism
that characterizes Nietzsche's thought. The problem of truth constitutes the
principal frontier between art and science, in the very conception of
philosophy as a tertium quid, a third
genre that resists all systematic classification, for at the same time that it
is presented as art (techne) in its
ends and productions (poiesis), it is
expressed through the mediation of concepts like a science (episteme).[7] For
Nietzsche, the philosopher is the man of tomorrow and the day after tomorrow
insofar as he always finds himself in contradiction to his today (JGB 212; cf.
211). The philosopher is the physician, the artist, and legislator who says yes
(Ja-sagen) to the becoming of man
through the active, creative overcoming of himself, the self-overcoming of his
own moral values and his systems of truth. Therefore, there is no dialectical
or transcendental method appropriate to philosophy, since all methods betray
always already a certain will to truth. (JGB §§ 35,36) One can only speak of
"methods" in an immanent, practical sense, by turning the very
pathways (hodoi) that take one beyond
(meta) their safe origins and
destination into an effective undergoing of life. To paraphrase Heidegger, human
beings are always already unterwegs, en route, in their pre-given relations
of appropriation vis-à-vis their being, thinking, and speaking. Thus, Nietzsche
places the question of truth on the same level of problematization as the
question of method, in particular, the subjectivity that betrays the impartial,
impersonal ideal of methodical quests:
The
will to truth which will still tempt us to many a venture, that famous
truthfulness of which all philosophers so far have spoken with respect --what
questions has this will to truth not laid before us! (...) Who is it really that puts questions to us here? What in us really wants
"truth"? (JGB § 1)
In
order to show that genealogy can be regarded as a critical principle of
interpretation in Nietzsche, it is important to place it first within the
broader context of Nietzsche's thought, and then proceed to see to what extent
it constitutes the central problematic of his philosophy. This means, before
anything, that some unity has been presupposed, not necessarily a systematic
one, but a certain coherence of thought in the aphorismatic work of an original
thinker such as Nietzsche. The first great interpreters of Nietzsche, such as
Karl Jaspers (Nietzsche: Einführung in
das Verständnis seines Philosophierens, 1936) and Karl Löwith (Nietzsches Philosophie der Ewigen
Wiederkunft des Gleichen, 1935), had already to face up to the
"contradictions" inherent to the Nietzschean thought, and they
offered solutions that strike us today as leaving much to be desired, such as
the resort to a "real dialectic" or a primordial return to the
Presocratics, respectively. Walter Kaufmann was one of the first to refute such
facile solutions, in a book that would become a bestseller, in spite of all its
shortcomings --(Nietzsche: Philosopher,
Psychologist, Antichrist, 1950).[8] It was
then established that in order to fully understand and do justice to the work
of Nietzsche one had to take into account not only the exegetical work on the
whole of his writings (including Der
Wille zur Macht and the entire collection of Nachlaß), but also its interpretation as Nietzsche himself
supposedly expected to be read (a Nietzschean hermeneutics). With the
publication of Heidegger's polemic Vorlesungen
(1936-40) and Abhandlungen (1940-46)
in 1961, the importance of a self-interpretation of Nietzschean texts --in
particular, the Will to Power-- was
once again emphasized. As in the Talmudic and Lutheran traditions, Nietzsche
was to be read in the light of the whole of its own textuality, scriptura sui ipsius interpres. It was
only following its post-Heideggerian reception in France (with Pierre
Klossowski, Gilles Deleuze, Michel Foucault, Sarah Kofman, Jacques Derrida,
Eric Blondel, Michel Haar, and others), that a genuine interest in an
interpretative "principle" arose. It has become since then
insufferable the misreading of existentialist and dialectical features into
Nietzsche, and even Heideggerian glosses have become rather dispensable. The
"New Nietzsche," as David Allison remarks, "asks the reader to
consider the general conditions of life --its prognosis for advance and
decline, its strength or weakness, its general etiology --as well as that of
its sustaining culture and values."(NN xiii) In order to approach the
Nietzschean corpus, the careful reader needs both "a theory of
interpretation understood as a general semiotics" and a "genealogical
analysis."(NN xvi) As it will be seen throughout the next sections,
Foucault was such a reader of Nietzsche, both as a hermeneute of suspicion and
as a genealogist of modernity.
To
paraphrase Gadamer, it could be said that the hermeneutic problem in Nietzsche
could be formulated in terms of truth and method, considering that it was
Nietzsche, as Deleuze has pointed out, the first thinker--even before Frege and
Husserl, and long before the analytical schools of language-- to have
introduced in philosophy and in a correlative manner the concepts of meaning (Sinn/Bedeutung) and value (Wert).[9]
According to Deleuze, it is precisely in Nietzsche's philosophy and not in
Kant's that we find the means, both theoretical and practical, to carry out the
critique tout court.Such was the very
thesis appropriated and reformulated by Foucault, undoubtedly one of the
greatest interpreters of Nietzsche in the last decades. As Gadamer himself has
remarked in response to Habermas's charges, our experience of language
--including its systematic aspects of rationality-- and our experience in the
world --including the Lebenswelt--are
co-originary and simply cannot be dissociated.[10] As will
be shown, that constitutes a fundamental thesis of Nietzsche's philosophy, and
failing to understand it may result in misunderstanding his perspectivism and
aestheticism. I am following Allan Megill's usage of the term
"aestheticism," as applied to both Nietzsche and Foucault, as it
refers "not to the condition of being enclosed within the limited
territory of the aesthetic, but rather to an attempt to explain the aesthetic
to embrace the whole of reality."[11] In
light of many passages where Nietzsche spouses this aestheticist view of
reality (i.e. GT "Attempt at Self-Criticism" § 5, WP passim), we can
better understand Nietzsche's critique of Kant's désintéressement in the third Critique.(GM
III § 6) Long before Heidegger, Foucault, and Derrida, Nietzsche attacked the
hypostatizing conceptualization of fictions such as Man, Culture, or History,
to account for the bridging of nature and spirit, phenomena and noumena. And
yet, I will argue that Nietzsche's aestheticism differs from Heidegger's
precisely because of the former's refusal to yield to new forms of mysticism or
eschatological expectations. Not even a god can save us, according to
Nietzsche, not even the overcoming of metaphysics would deliver us from the
completion of nihilism. Heidegger's aestheticism conceives of the will to power
as an artwork, so as to comprise all
that Nietzsche understands by truth. I will question this reductionist
formulation, insofar as it eclipses other important aspects of the will to
truth that Foucault has appropriated in his own genealogy of modernity and, in
particular, in an aesthetic conception of the relationship between ethics and
politics.
As
opposed to Kant's reduction of truth to a propositional correspondence of the
categories to the cognitive faculty of understanding, Nietzsche sought to
rescue a pre-theoretical, nontranscendental aesthetics that allows for the
appearing of beings to remain on the surface of being, without any resort to a
suprasensible, noumenal realm that accounts for the possibility of their
cognition. In JGB § 11, Nietzsche recognizes the tremendous influence that Kant
exerted on German philosophy --tainted with the comical niaiserie allemande-- by the very introduction of the cognitive
faculties of the mind. Above all, it was the suprasensible --which, as
Nietzsche rightly remarked, inspired Schelling's "intellectual
intuition" (and Hegel's critique of Kant)-- that betrayed the veritable virtus dormitiva ("sleepy
faculty") of Kant's attempt to base truth on transcendental
grounds--"Vermöge eines Vermögens"
("by virtue of some virtue"). In order to awake the senses once
again, and anticipating Foucault's overcoming of Kant's "anthropological
slumber," Nietzsche calls for new philosophers to create, with the hammer,
new values and new truths: "Genuine
philosophers, however, are commanders and legislators: they say, 'thus it shall be!'" And he adds,
"Their 'knowing' is creating,
their creating is a legislation, their will to truth is --will to power."(JGB § 212) Nietzsche's antidote is their
remedy, just as the real and the true are the appearing of what is always a
shadow, a false reverse. Nietzsche had already addressed the question
"what is truth?," in an oft-quoted paragraph from an 1873 Nachlaß, Über Wahrheit und Lüge im aussermoralischen Sinne, that unmasks the
perspectivism of every knowledge:
What,
then, is truth? A mobile army of metaphors, metonyms, and anthropomorphisms
--in short, a sum of human relations, which have been enhanced, transposed, and
embellished poetically and rhetorically, and which after long use seems firm,
canonical, and obligatory to a people: truths are illusions about which one has
forgotten that this is what they are...
Commenting
on this passage and comparing it with classical definitions of rhetoric, Derrida
has shown how Nietzsche sought to take his distances from philosophical
interpretations of the concept of truth and conceptual philosophizing --as
metaphor subverts the generative role of philosophical concept.[12] As over
against the rule of the Aristotelian-Hegelian metaphor of the intelligible (ousia, geistig) over the sensible (phainomena,
sinnlich), according to which certain
philosophemes conquer a conceptual privilege, Derrida finds inspiration in
Nietzsche to propound metaphoricity as nonconcept --an effect of différance-- expressing thus "what
is proper to man," in this perpetual metaphorein
(transposing, transferring, transforming, "la relève de la
métaphore") of appropriating and expropriating what is his own--language,
rationality, thinking. Hermeneutics is thus radicalized into
"deconstruction," so that every meaning is always already (toujours déjà, immer schon) an effect of interpretations. Although I do not intend
to examine how Derrida's reading of Nietzsche (and Heidegger) leads us to the Abbau of metaphysical traditions to be
re-interpreted, I must signal the relevance of the metaphor and the correlation
between semiology (or semiotics) and ontology for a full understanding of
Foucault's reading of Nietzsche. That will be fully elaborated in the third
chapter, by invoking Foucault's essay on "Nietzsche, Freud, Marx," at
the threshold of the era of the hermeneutics of suspicion in post-existential
In
the above-mentioned essay on truth, Nietzsche articulates also the "drive
to truth" in terms of the instinctive need that makes possible for human
beings to survive as social beings, out of "the obligation to lie
according to a fixed convention,to lie herd-like in a style obligatory for
all." However conventionalist and relativist, this Nietzschean
formulation, very reminiscent of the Hobbesian pactum, should not be taken prima
facie, as some sort of irrationalist creed but as an expression of his
philosophical perspectivism, thoroughly consistent with his view of the world
as human interpretation. That modern, European man, after thousands of years
has reached a certain state of self-consciousness, in which his existence makes
sense, according to Nietzsche, proves nothing else than the all-too human wish
that such a sense is true and founded. After all, nothing can assure us that
the human species will be preserved forever --that the fate of humans will be
different, say, from that of the dinosaurs or other extinguished species. If
rationality --and sociability, for that matter-- distinguishes us from other
species, that remains all the same an effect and not a cause, "a means for
the preservation of the individual"(§ 1) and not an end in itself. In
effect, Nietzsche does not advocate any promise of "improving" humankind
(EH Preface § 1), for in this consists what has been called thus far morals
(cf. Twilight of Idols "The
'Improvers' of Humankind" § 2). The taming, breeding, weakening,
sickening, and catechizing of the human beast, which Christianity so arrogantly
acclaims as a civilizing "improvement" of humanity, anticipates in
Nietzsche what Foucault would later develop as the practices of subjectivation
that, through normalizing and disciplinary techniques, consolidates the
formation of modern subjects. The Nietzschean genealogy, as a radical critique
that problematizes the epistemological delimitations of a method and of a
system of universal truths, stems thus from a calling into question (remise en question), historically and
culturally situated --decadent Europe of fin
de siècle--, philosophically formulated around the old question: "Who
are we?" Even a superficial reading of Nietzsche's major texts brings to
the fore the theme of the human condition and humankind, in its relation to all
the other themes of his works, even if such a thematization takes on a grave
timbre, that is, as a theme to be unmasked, demythologized, and overcome. Not
without reason, Nietzsche has been more known for the metaphor of the
"Overman" (Übermensch) than
any other concept. In effect, the transvaluation of values, nihilism, the death
of God, the eternal return, and the will to power are all thematically related
with the problem of the self-overcoming of man (die Selbstüberwindung des Menschen). Thus, the anti-humanism of
Nietzsche's critique of religion, morals, and metaphysics is rooted in a
philosophy directed towards the future, without delineating, however, any
utopian, eschatological, or messianic horizons. "Who, then, amidst these
dangers besetting our age, will pledge his services as sentinel and champion of
humankind[Menschlichkeit]?,"
asks Nietzsche, "Who will
raise the image of man [das Bild des Menschen] when everyone
feels in himself the worm of selfishness and a jackal terror, and has fallen
from that image into bestiality and even robot automatism?"(Third Unmodern Observation, "Schopenhauer
As Educator" § 4) Nietzsche seems to be thus engaged in a prophetic
mission, with the conviction of a Daniel or a Jeremiah, predestined to announce
the tragic fate that is about to assail nations and tribes. However apocalyptic
it may sound, like many other of his texts, Nietzsche's atonality forbids any
stylistic harmonization in function of a determinate literary genre or
philosopheme. Hence the apparent oppositions (e.g., the Apollinean vs. the
Dionysian, the Socratic vs. the tragic) which will only be overcome by the
affirmation of the amor fati, the
Nietzschean formula for greatness in a human being: "that one wants
nothing to be different, not forward, not backward, not in all eternity. Not
merely bear what is necessary...but love
it."(EH "Why I am so clever" § 10) Such is, wihtout doubt, the
only sollen of human nature, which
Nietzsche translates in autobiographical manner in the Ecce Homo: "How to become what one is." The aphorisms of
the Nachlaß "Die Unschuld des
Werdens," dedicated to the composition of Zarathustra[13] reveal
the "anthropological" character of the will to power, conceived as
that which makes both cosmology and ontology possible, correlate to the eternal
return of the Same.
It
is important to add that, in this Nietzschean context, "anthropology"
cannot be mistaken for a metaphysical, philosophical conception of human
nature, for the place of the anthropos
vis-à-vis the kosmos is not that of a
cognitive opposition between subject and object (Kant's Gegenstand), since human-being is always displaced by its
becoming-in-the-world. For the world itself, according to Nietzsche, "the
world viewed from the inside, the world defined and determined according to its
'intelligible character'" --to parody Kant-- is "'the will to power'
and nothing else."(JGB §36) If one discounts the dangerous rigor of
formulas of proportionality, one may say that the will to power is for being
what the eternal return is for the becoming of the same. Being human is to
become in the world what one should be in one's self-overcoming. "Der
Mensch ist etwas, das überwunden werden soll"-- "man is something
that ought to be overcome" --, such is the motto of Nietzsche's magnum
opus, Thus Spake Zarathustra (see,
for instance, Z Vorrede 3, Vom Krieg und Kriegsvolke, passim), and of the
Nietzschean opera in general (cf. JGB
§ 257; GM II 10, III 27; EH Z 6, Z 8, IV 5; WM 804, 983, 1001, 1051, 1027,
1060). The will to power itself is decisively introduced as will to overcome
oneself (cf. Z Part II, esp. "Von der Selbstüberwindung"), not as the
psychological will à la Schopenhauer, but as the cosmological expression of the
eternal return (cf. Z Parts III and IV, esp. "Von alten und neuen Tafeln")
and from this follows all understanding of Nietzsche's philosophy. Thus, method
and truth in the Nietzschean conception of the humanum cannot be dissociated from the sense and value assigned to
human existence itself, both in ontological and cosmological terms. As we will see,
genealogy fulfills the triple task of critique as applied to the analysis of
Western European culture, and can thus be seen as a method of cultural,
historical diagnosis.
2. Human Nature and the Will to Power
Was es mit unsrer Heiterkeit auf sich hat.
Das größte neuere Ereignis --daß "Gott tot ist," daß der Glaube an
den christlichen Gott unglaubwürdig geworden ist-- beginnt bereits seine ersten
Schatten über Europa zu werfen. (...) In der Hauptsache aber darf man sagen;
das Ereignis selbst ist viel zu groß, zu fern, zu abseits vom Fassungsvermögen
vieler, als daß auch nur seine Kunde schon angelangt
heißen dürfte... (FW § 343)
The
death of God is, for Nietzsche, the greatest of all the monumental events of
European modernity, the most significant of all, and this is to be taken both
in a metaphysical and cultural-historical sense. It must thus call into
question a Heideggerian reading that concludes --for reasons intrinsic to
Heidegger's ontological hermeneutics-- that "Nietzsche himself interprets the
course of Western history metaphysically and in truth as the ascension and
development of nihilism."[14] Now,
Heidegger reduces the Nietzschean work to an immanent critique of metaphysics
which, precisely because it remains within its historicity, cannot overcome
metaphysical thinking, in its very ontotheological, nihilistic constitution.
The "will to power," according to Heidegger, must thus figure among
the greatest metaphysical motifs of Western philosophy, such as the Platonic eidos, the Cartesian substantia, and the Kantian Ding an sich. Just as Marx could not do
away with Hegelian dialectics, Nietzsche would have at most reversed the
transcendental epistemology of Kant, without succeeding in thinking its essence
in a post-metaphysical gesture. To a large extent, Foucault's work has
challenged these blind spots of Heidegger's reading of Nietzsche, ultimately
guided by a reduction of the "will to power" to the Sein des Seienden. For the purpose of
the present study, there is still another aspect that marks off Foucault's
reading of Nietzsche from Heidegger's, and that deserves our attention.
Commenting on the famous passage on the death of God (FW § 125, Der tolle Mensch, comlemented by § 343),
Heidegger signals the sense of "madness" on the part of the man who
proclaims the death of God, to be distinguished from the
"foolishness" of denying God as an unbeliever. As for Foucault, he is
rather concerned with madness as a broader phenomenon of subjectivation, so
that a psychiatric reading of this passage should not exclude a theological
one, nor the social analysis minimize its juridical aspects, but the very
definitions of madness (Wahnsinn) and
unreason (Irrsinn) are to be called
into question, since they were also constituted in the historical process of subject-formations.[15] At any rate, the expression
"madman" is used by Nietzsche as a parody to the allusion by the
Psalmist to the "fool" who says in his heart: "There is no
God" (Psalm 14:1). In the original context --which Nietzsche
metaphorically transposes in grand style--, the word of the Psalmist (in
Hebrew, naval) refers to the
unrighteous and to the unbeliever --whoever does not believe in God, turns out
to be a fool, a madman. This is the same sense that will be later transvalued (umwerten) by Paul to contrast, in a
world of unbelievers, the "folly of God" with the "wisdom of
men"(1 Corinthians 1:18-25) and, on the eve of modernity, by Luther and
Pascal, in the radical opposition between theology and philosophy ("Le
dieu d'Abraham, d'Isaac et de Jacob n'est point le dieu des philosophes").
The madman who in a bright morning lit a lantern and ran to the market place,
screaming "I seek God!," cannot be thus identified with Nietzsche
himself or even with the character "Zarathustra" --as Heidegger seems
to suggest.[16]
To be sure, the madman appears as the messenger of an event (the death of God),
that he himself interprets as a metaphysical problem:
The
Madman. Have you not heard of that
madman who lit a lantern in the bright morning hours, ran to the market place,
and cried incessantly, "I seek God! I seek God!" As many of those who
do not believe in God were standing around just then, he provoked much
laughter. Why, did he get lost? said one. Did he lose his way like a child?
said another. Or is he hiding? Is he afraid of us? Has he gone on a voyage? or
emigrated? Thus they yelled and laughed. The madman jumped into their midst and
pierced them with his glances.
"Whither
is God?" he cried. "I shall tell you. We have killed him ‑‑you and I. All of us are his
murderers. But how have we done this? How were we able to drink up the sea? Who
gave us the sponge to wipe away the entire horizon? What did we do when we
unchained this earth from its sun? Whither is it moving now? Whither are we
moving now? Away from all suns? Are we not plunging continually? Backward,
sideward, forward, in all directions? Is there any up or down left? Are we not
straying as through an infinite nothing? Do we not feel the breath of empty
space? Has it not become colder? Is not night and more night coming on all the
while? Must not lanterns be lit in the
morning? Do we not hear anything yet of the noise of the gravediggers who are
burying God? Do we not smell anything yet of God's decomposition? Gods too
decompose. God is dead. God remains dead. And we have killed him. (FW § 125)
Madness
appears here as a limit-experience of a rationality in crisis, with the
secularizing collapse of the belief in a foundation that bestows meaning to
human existence, the belief that there must be transcendent grounds for
ultimate values. Kant's transcendental criticism, as a true representative of
the aufgeklärte philosophy, was
decisive for this event, with its refusal of dogmatic, metaphysical solutions
to the antinomies of cosmology, psychology, anthropology, and theology. But
Nietzsche also questions Kant's critique of reason precisely at the systematic
level that accounts for a practical assurance of pure reason, following the
critique of theoretical reason. Even if one cannot prove God's existence or
even if God never existed, human reason can always create one and live as if
there were such a being. That reason cannot account for its other, that it
cannot transgress its theoretical and practical uses, is a clear symptom of its
incapacity to judge its own fateful breakdown. It takes a madman to proclaim,
however naive it may sound, that God is dead. It takes a madman to proclaim,
despite all nonsense, the greatest triumph of modern reason in its endless wars
against fear, superstition, and dogma. Nietzsche is certainly using a
metaphorical language, but the rather raw description of the putrefaction of a
divine corpse signals the proximity and historicity of this tremendous cultural
event. After all, we modern men are the ones who killed God. We --the
legitimate heirs of the Judaeo-Christian tradition that built up the scenarios
of Western civilizations-- are the very ones who submitted ourselves to the
yoke of a divine creator and judge. Nietzsche's transvaluation cannot thus be
reduced to a mere reversal of values, such as Feuerbach's antitheological
manifesto (homo homini deus est) or
Marx's critique of ideology (camera
obscura, Wirklichkeit versus Vorstellung),not even to a Heideggerian Umkehrung of metaphysics or self-proclaimed
Überwindung of Western metaphysics.[17] It is, therefore, an effect of the
self-overcoming (Selbstüberwindung)
of humankind, as the outcome of civilizing processes, with religion appearing
as the major expression of this "experience of the history of humanity as
a whole" taken individually, above all in the Judaeo-Christian conception
of a Heilsgeschichte ("history
of salvation"). "This godlike feeling," writes Nietzsche,
"would then be called --humaneness" ("Dieses göttliche Gefühl
hieße dann--Menschlichkeit!" (FW § 337 "Die zukünftige
'Menschlichkeit'"). The modern feeling for one's own participation in
universal history, the humanist sense of historical belonging, is what
Nietzsche's "history of the present" seeks to unfold in his critique
of idealism. The genealogy of Christianity occupies an important place in this
radical critique of modernity, although the critique of religion in Nietzsche
does not lead to the foundation of a new secular kingdom (Feuerbach) or to a
positive critique of politics (Marx), but rather to the self-fulfillment and
serenity (Heiterkeit), which is the
true meaning of the "joie de vivre" of a creative, free spirit and of
the Gay Science.(cf. §§ 290,
343) For Zaratustra, "God is a
conjecture [Mutmaßung]," but
because it cannot be limited to what is thinkable (begrenzt sei in der Denkbarkeit) it deserves to be dealt with as a
sickness and vertigo. The Übermensch,
on the other hand, can be thought and it is within our reach to create it out
by willing our self-overcoming. "Willing liberates [Wollen befreit]: that is the true teaching of will and
liberty."(Z II "Upon the Blessed Isles") Still in the same
passage, Zaratustra exclaims: "Away from God and gods this will [to
create] has lured me; what could one create if gods existed?" And he adds,
"But my fervent will to create impels me ever again toward man; thus is
the hammer impelled toward the stone." For Nietzsche, creation, in the
broader sense of poiesis, is the true
vocation of human beings in the full exercise of their freedom, through their
will to power, in an active manner, not reactive, without the resentment that
characterizes religious man. As will be seen, Foucault's interpretation of
Nietzsche does full justice to the latter's aestheticism without reducing it to
a passe-partout hermeneutics but
rather stressing the poiesis of
"giving style to someone's character" [seinem Charakter "Stil geben"], in a self-stylizing,
polyphonic aesthetics of existence that multiplies ad infinitum the relations of codification and decodification of
every experience --taken as fact or human interpretation. The death of God is,
therefore, a paradigm of such a critical gesture, at the levelling of facts and
interpretations, in the same historical event.
On
the other hand, the death of God may be interpreted as the sign of times of
modernity, as the triumph of autonomy and the emancipation of human reason
announce the imminence of the Great Noon, the fullness of the three great
metamorphoses of the camel, the lion, and the child (cf. Z II "Von den
drei Verwandlungen" and IV "Das Zeichen"). The collapse of
rationality --understood as "the discipline of their minds [die Zucht ihres Kopfes]"-- would
be, for Nietzsche, nothing less than "the eruption of madness [Irrsinn],... the eruption of arbitrariness
[Belieben] in feeling, seeing, and
hearing, the enjoyment of the mind's lack of discipline [Zuchtlosigkeit des Kopfes], the joy in human unreason [die Freunde am Menschen-Unverstande]."(FW
§ 76) Humankind up to our days has lived in full agreement, like friends, with
the "healthy common sense" (gesunder
Menschen-verstand)--a question of survival. The man of the future,
according to the same paragraph, since he is even more aware of this
conventionalism, is led to suspicion and unbelief. Thus, neither truth nor
certainty are the opposite of unreason or madness, but "the universality
and the universal binding force of a faith [die
Allgemeinheit und Allverbindlichkeit eines Glaubens]; in sum, the
non-arbitrary character of judgments [das
Nicht-Beliebige im Urteilen]." Therefore, if Nietzsche celebrates
madness in the carnival of the death of God, it is because it inaugurates a new
dawn of the "de-deification da nature": When will we complete our de-deification of
nature? When may we begin to "naturalize"
humanity in terms of a pure, newly discovered, newly redeemed nature?[Wann
werden wir die Natur ganz entgöttlicht haben! Wann werden wir anfangen dürfen,
uns Menschen mit der reinen, neu gefundenen, neu erlösten Natur zu vernatürlichen!" (FW § 109)
The
project of reintegrating human nature into cosmological nature --different,
say, from the humanization of nature proposed
by the young Marx-- cannot be dissociated from the Nietzschean motif of the death of God. The
paragraphs 108 through 125 of the Gay Science
constitute, in effect, the immediate context that culminates with the death of
God, namely, the dedeification of nature, whose religious context is clearly
articulated in cosmological terms and not exclusively historico-ontological
--as would result from a reading that privileges the history of metaphysics in
the Will to Power. We see thus that the question of rationality
and modernity refers to a complex anthropological problematic, where the
critique of value and meaning requires a careful exam of different correlative
aspects --including the problems of an epistemological, political, and ethical
order. I will conclude this section with an allusion to the critique of
religion in the Will to Power.
After
the composition of the Twilight of Ídols
in 1888, in the last year of his literary production prior to his mental
collapse, Nietzsche seemed to have abandoned the project of publishing a
collection of aphorisms called Der Wille
zur Macht, and decided to write a book, Versuch
einer Umwertung aller Werte (subtitle of WM), composed of four essays, of
which only one, the Antichrist was
completed, together with the preface. The final edition of over one thousand
notes by Nietzsche (1883-1888) that compose this majestoso Nachlaß was carefully undertaken by his friend Peter Gast in 1906.
It is interesting to recapitulate the division of the work into four books:
I.
European Nihilism
II.
Critique of Highest Values Hitherto
III.
Principles of a New Valuation
IV.
Discipline and Breeding
The
first subdivision of the Second Book, "Critique of Religion," as
Kaufmann remarked, provided great part of the material for the composition of
the Antichrist. The Nietzschean
critique of religion is itself divided into three parts,
1.
Genesis of Religions
2.
History of Christianity
3.
Christian Ideals
The
correlation between power and the formation of subjects (WM § 135), the themes
of priestly religiosity, slave morality, pessimistic nihilism (§ 156), ressentiment (§ 167), the transition from
Judaism to Christianity (§ 181, passim), the herd morality, Paul's psychology
(§§ 171, 173), castration (§ 204), self-denial, to sum up, the transvaluation
of values, is developed according to the same logic found in Beyond Good and Evil and in the Genealogy of Morals. It must be noted,
however, that the context stresses the social-historical aspects of the
evolution of religious phenomena in relation to nihilism. This
historical-metaphysical background may thus favor a Heideggerian reading as
long as we do not fall prey to a structuralist imposition of a grille de lecture to the textual
totality of the Nietzschean work, as in a methodical formalization.[18]
No
doubt, the clear connection between the death of God and the collapse of the
cosmic order (FW § 125) --understood as an interpretation of human nature--
indicates that Nietzsche is invoking here the Judaeo-Christian God the Creator
of heavens and earth, the causa prima,
the metaphysical God of theism --with the transition from the Hebrew to the
Greek constituting the cultural background to the transvaluation of
religion.(cf. AC §§ 37-45) In another aphorism (FW § 343), opening the Fifth
Book ("We Fearless Ones") added to the second edition of the Gay Science in 1886, Nietzsche affirms
"that God is dead" to mean "that the belief in the Christian god
has become unbelievable" --giving sequence to the incipit tragoedia of the last paragraph of the Fourth Book,
identical to the first chapter of the Prologue of Zarathustra. The death of God signals, therefore, the threshold of
tragedy, to be rediscovered in the infinite horizon of seas never sailed before
--cf. FW §§ 124, 281, 283, 289, 291, with allusions to
3. Nietzsche's Critique of Kantian Morality
Die christliche Moralität selbst,
der immer strenger genommene Begriff der Wahrhaftigkeit, die
Beichväter-Feinheit des christlichen Gewissens, übersetzt und sublimiert zum
wissenschaftlichen Gewissen, zur intellektuellen Sauberkeit a jeden Preis. Die
Natur ansehn, als ob sie ein Beweis für die Güte und Obhut eines Gottes sei;
die Geschichte interpretieren zu Ehren einer göttlichen Vernunft, als
beständiges Zeugnis einer sittlichen Weltordnung und sittlicher
Schlußabsichten; die eignen Erlebnisse auslegen, wie sie fromme Menschen lange
genug ausgelegt haben, wie als ob alles Fügung, alles Wink, alles Heil der
Seele zuliebe ausgedacht und geschikt sei: das ist nunmehr vorbei, das hat das Gewissen gegen
sich, das gilt allen feineren Gewissen als unanständig, unehrlich, als
Lügnerei, Feminismus, Schwachheit, Feigheit --mit dieser Strenge, wenn irgend
womit, sind wir eben guter Europäer
und Erben von Europas längster und tapferster Selbstüberwindung... (GM III §
27; FW § 357)
The
long citation --self-citation of an author that overcomes himself-- is invoked
by Nietzsche as he formulates the "law of life" (das Gesetz des Lebens) as "a law of necessary 'self-overcoming' that is in the essence of life [das Gesetz der notwendigen "Selbstüberwindung"
im Wesen des Lebens]," to wit, that "[a]ll great things bring
about their own destruction through an act self-overcoming [Alle großen Dinge gehen durch sich selbst
zugrunde, durch einen Akt der Selbst-aufhebung]." (GM III § 27) This
great Nietzschean thesis is certainly implicit in his doctrines of the will to
power and of the transvaluation of all values --as Nietzsche himself saw it in
allusion to the "work that he was preparing [ein Werk, das ich vorbereite: "Der
Wille zur Macht." Versuch einer Umwertung aller Werte]." In the
three essays explicitly dedicated to the critique of morality --the critique of
the morality of ressentiment
(Christianity), critique of the self-conscious, autonomous morality (Kant), and
the critique of the ascetic ideal (nihilism) (cf. EH GM)--, Nietzsche
undertakes in a quasi-methodic fashion his project of transvaluation as a new
demand for the self-overcoming of "modern man": "we need a critique of moral values, the value of these values themselves must
first be called into question."(GM Preface § 6) And, in order to
accomplish this, one needs a "genealogy," a formulation of the
knowledge of the conditions and circumstances of the birth of morality, as a wirkliche Historie der Moral,
"gray" --as the document, in opposition to the pristine, spiritual
"blue"(§ 7)--, in brief, a historical critique and a critical history
that are immanent or, in Foucault's words, "a form of history which can
account for the constitution of knowledges (savoirs),
discourses (discours), domains of
objects, etc., without having to make reference to a subject, which is either
transcendental in relation to the field of events, or runs in its empty
sameness throughout the course of history."(FR 59). Genealogy is thus
presented as the climax of a critique of morals, already outlined and partially
elaborated in Beyond Good and Evil(1886),
though in these two books Kant's morality is approached in a more systematic
fashion than in the Gay Science. The
critique of morals emerges not so much as the logical moment that follows the
suppression of religion, but as being adjacent to the very genealogy of modern
man. Modernity cannot conceal, therefore, the moral character that constitutes
itself as such, in that "'autonomous' and 'moral' are mutually exclusive,"
according to Nietzsche --contra Kant.(GM II § 2) On the other hand, Nietzsche seeks to rescue
a positive conception of modern man in the anticipation of the Übermensch that must be celebrated
today, in the ought of this innocent becoming that is the self-overcoming of
man. Thus, whatever is "moral" is precisely what ought to be overcome
in the conception of humanity that culminated with German idealism. The
atheist, creative thinking of the modern "free spirit" is to be thus opposed
to theistic, metaphysical thought, no longer guided and limited by religious
belief. In this Kant and Nietzsche share the same conviction that it is
necessary to use one's own understanding, sapere
aude, so that the spirit of freedom be fulfilled --despite all the
divergences as for the meaning of such ideal of freedom, overall in the
concepts of "will" and "free will." Rousseau, Voltaire, and
French enlightened philosophes would
have been a common source for both Nietzsche and Kant, in their undertaking of a
critical philosophy. Nevertheless, Nietzsche's attitude toward the Aufklärung --frequently cited as an
example of his supposed irrationalism and anti-modernism-- differs from Kant's
not only in its political implications, but also in its historical, philosophical
presuppositions. The question of morals is thus decisive for a correct
evaluation of these divergences.
In
principle, Kant is upheld by Nietzsche as the great champion of the
philosophical struggle against the optimism of naïve realism, precisely by
having raised phenomena to the status of reality --just as Schopenhauer
transvalue them into Vorstellungen
(cf. GT §§ 18,19). In 1886, in the preface to the second edition of Morgenröte, Nietzsche denounces the
seduction of morals in Kant, the belief that cannot be founded upon its own
conception of history and nature (M Pref. § 3). In the same book, Nietzsche
criticizes Kant for the dichotomy of sensible and non-sensible in the
conception of moral man (M §§ 132,481), but seems to remain faithful to the
ideal of Aufklärung:
This
Enlightenment we must now carry further forward: let us not worry about the
"great revolution" and the "great reaction" against it which have taken place --they are
no more than the sporting of waves in comparison with the truly great flood
which bears us along! (M § 197)
Nietzsche
identifies himself, therefore, with the critical thrust of Kant's philosophy,
to the extent that it does not fall back into an ascetic ideal, typical of
Christian morality (M § 339), which would have been supposedly overcome in
Kant's own critique of metaphysics. In effect, it is precisely against the
Kantian idea of "progress," reappropriated by Hegel, that Nietzsche
undertakes his genealogical critique, already anticipated in the Second
Unmodern Observation ("Vom Nutzen und Nachteil der Historie für
Leben," 1874). What is at stake, therefore, is the articulation of
historicity and humanity so as to avoid the subordination of human development
to the logic of progress and the transcendental foundations of morals. As
Nietzsche criticizes the utilitarianist conception of Paul Rée (GM Preface §
4,7), it is not only the evolutionist historicism that he seeks to combat but
above all the metaphysical, supra-historical perspective that subtly guides historiography.
Thus, one of the greatest contributions of Nietzsche consists in having
denounced a conception of history that presupposes a transcendental unity
--typical of the soteriological reading of Christianity. Nietzsche unmasks,
therefore, Kantian morality as the return to what had already been overcome by
the Aufklärung, namely, faith in
whatever cannot be thought--for religion itself, according to Kant, does not
seek to know God in the same way one claims to know nature. This is outlined in
the second part of the Second Book of WM (§§ 253-405, "Critique of
Morality"):
1.
Origin of Moral Valuations
2.
The Herd
3.
General Remarks on Morality
4.
How Virtue is Made to Dominate
5.
The Moral Ideal
6.
Further Considerations for a Critique of Morality
The
entire question of morality, according to Nietzsche, has been reformulated as a
question of faith, as the subtle, dogmatic ideal that remains faithful to the
"beyond" --from Plato to Kant and Hegel. Nietzsche's main thesis,
following the equivalence between Leben
and Wille zur Macht (WM § 254), is
thus enunciated: "there are no moral
phenomena, there is only a moral interpretation of these phenomena. This
interpretation itself is of extra-moral origin."(WM § 258) We are thus
transposed into the semiological problem of the metaphor --what may well be
discarded as a vicious circle in an ontological hermeneutic, depending on the
perspective adopted. I have adopted a critical, textual hermeneutic that simply
refers us back to the context of the previous discussion on truth and metaphor:
there are no universals in the Nietzschean lexicon. The "extra-moral origin" is only
the reversal of morals, the immorality of resentment and of all other desiderata of ideals forged for humanity
(WM §§ 266, 373, 390), supposedly meant for a "better" humanity. Such
is the great pia fraus of the
Christian religion. The critique of religion and the critique of morals
presuppose the conception of sense and value --such as in the formula
"good and evil"-- that should not escape the boundaries of critique,
as if it were some sort of "immaculate conception."[20] The
evacuation of the divine, contrary to a Hegelian kenosis that finds its fullness through the positive work of the
negative, does not suscitate any hope of reconciliation. The nihilism is a
radical, irreversible event:
What does nihilism
mean? That the highest values devaluate
themselves. The aim is lacking; "why?" finds no answer.
Radical nihilism is the conviction of an absolute untenability of
existence when it comes to the highest values one recognizes; plus the
realization that we lack the least right to posit a beyond or an in‑itself
of things that might be "divine" or morality incarnate. This
realization is a consequence of the cultivation of "truthfulness" ‑‑thus
itself a consequence of the faith in morality. (WP § 3)
The
radical critique that Nietzsche undertakes against Christian morality provides
us with the methodological clue and the very Sache of his experimentalism, still in the "Versuch einer
Umwertung aller Werte." Simply by not having nothing (nihil) beyond God, once the true, the good, and the beautiful are
necessarily transvalued with the death of God. The same fate is, in effect,
reserved for the socialist and democratic systems. God is dead, therefore,
there is nothing to be grounded in, neither in moral nor in ontological terms.
It is not so much the question of having nothing beyond God, but of having no
fundamental "beyond" at all. All we have been left with is the
immanence of the world, co-originary with the innocent becoming of human
nature. Nothing else, nothing beyond, above or underneath us. Nothing is given
as principle or end, cause or reason to give meaning to what we are. To the
Kantian Paukenschlag that opposes
"the starry sky above me" to "the moral law within me" (KpV
A 288), Nietzsche proposes a gaya scienza
that transgresses the very boundaries of whatever is "outside" and
"inside," by the affirmation of a law without purity or end:
Sternen-Moral
Vorausbestimmt
zur Sternenbahn,
Was geht dich,
Stern, das Dunkel an?
Roll selig hin
durch diese Zeit!
Ihr Elend sei dir
fremd und weit!
Der fernsten Welt
gehört dein Schein:
Mitleid soll
Sünde für dich sein!
Nur ein Gebot gilt dir: sein rein![21]
4. Nietzsche and the Critique of Subjectivity
Es ist, wie man errät, nicht der Gegensatz von Subjekt und Objekt, der
The Provençal accent of the "
But we who are neither Jesuits nor
democrats, nor even German enough, we good
Europeans and free, very free
spirits --we still feel it, the whole need of the spirit and the whole tension
of its bow. And perhaps also the arrow, the task, and --who knows?--the goal
(JGB Preface)
It seems, therefore, that in spite
of all metaphoricity and of dissemination of signifiers, the text offers us the
interpretative project of a human existence. The fact that he speaks in the
first person of the plural(wir),including,
"with cynicism and innocence," the very author of this philosophical
prelude, already reveals the ethical, political relevance and the polemical
character of this collection of thoughts. The enigmatic style of Nietzsche
should not obfuscate our understanding of the subject-matter, to wit, whatever
constitutes the ultimate object of metaphysics, truth in the apprehension of
concepts of the world (cosmology), God(theology), and the
self(psychology/anthropology). It is not by chance that Nietzsche introduces in
the preface the theme of the book with the enigmatic, phallocentric words:
"Supposing truth is a woman..." The metaphor could not be more
aestheticist: that philosophers, from Plato through the German idealists --all
of them "men" (i.e. males),-- had failed in the art of seducing a
woman who never allowed to be conquered --truth as woman-object, la femme-vérité. The radicalism of
Nietzschean aestheticism does not reside, however, in the reduction of
philosophy to an aesthetic relation of appropriation and expropriation of the
beautiful and the true, but in the critical immanentism of his perspectivism.
If the philosopher is taken for an artiste
manqué, his failure consists precisely in seeking to transcend the world as
artwork, devaluing it as such. The Platonic opposition of sensible to the
intelligible, of which the mimesis-episteme opposition is the particular
case, permeates, according to the Nietzschean diagnosis, all the development of
a metaphysics of values that bridge the Aristotelian realism to Kantian
idealism:
Consider any morality [Moral] with this in mind: what there is
in it of "nature" teaches hatred of the laisser aller, of any all-too-great freedom, and implants the need
for limited horizons and the nearest tasks --teaching the narrowing of our perspective [Verengerung
der Perspektive], and thus in a certain sense stupidity, as a condition of
life and growth. "You should obey --someone and for a long time: else you will perish and lose the last
respect for yourself" --this appears to me to be the moral imperative of
nature which, to be sure, is neither "categorical" as the old Kant
would have it (hence the "else") nor addressed to the individual
(what do individuals matter to her?), but to people, races, ages, classes --but
above all to the whole human animal, to man.(JGB
§ 188)
Thus, in the first chapter, when
dealing with the "Prejudices of Philosophers," Nietzsche unmasks the
"will to truth" (der Wille zur
Wahrheit) by calling into question the value (Wert) of this will: "The fundamental faith of the
metaphysicians is the faith in opposite
values."(§ 2) The great question for Nietzsche is to determine the
motivation, the interest, the value of opposing a "no" to each
"yes," the opposition to the innocent becoming of the world, where
man is only a vector in a complex field of forces (§ 36, 230, 257). The reason
why Nietzsche's conception of agency is here reconstituted, together with its
correlative view of subjectivity and power, is to place the valuation of the
human being within a whole play of forces (Gesamtspiel),
where the will to power is defined as praxis,
pathos, physis, interpretation, self-reflection, and history. And yet the
will to power should not be reduced to the very becoming of being just as it
cannot be identified with a psychological substratum,[22]
as though Nietzsche were falling back into a naïve reformulation of the
metaphysical prima causa. To be sure,
the tension between a modern conception of the domination of nature (Hobbes)
and the Romantic conception of the harmonic return to nature (Rousseau) seems
to persist in the Nietzschean elaboration of the will to power --perhaps
because of his reading of Heraclitus and Parmenides. A careful reading of JGB
§§ 4, 10-12, and 16-19 leads us to the reformulation of the Nietzschean
question in the following terms: since the history of metaphysics cannot
provide us with a theory of power that isn't itself just another effect of this
history, i.e., of the reactive nihilism that underlies Western thought, a
critique of power must be placed elsewhere, so as to account for the
subjectivity of these theories and practices. Nietzsche proceeds thus to
critique the metaphysical conceptions of
agency (soul, free will, and will) so as to rescue classical notions of
rationality, freedom, and the will in one single, historicized concept of human
becoming. In effect, the will to power and genealogy are complementary
concepts, insofar as all cultural, historical genesis is effected in human
acting. The action-historicity
correlation is, in effect, recognized by Nietzsche as the two great legacies of
the German Aufklärung (WM § 1058):
The
two greatest philosophical points of view (devised by Germans):
a)
that of becoming, of development.
b) that according to the value of existence (but the wretched
form of German pessimism must first be overcome!)
To be sure, one does not find in
Kant the articulation between religion as a moral, cultural phenomenon, and the
historical self-consciousness --as we find it, say, in Hegel, largely due to
influence of Kant's writings on history.[23]
Once we understand the appropriation and reproduction of historical
determinations, action must be deteleologized, evacuated of all metaphysical logic
of progressus (GM II § 12). "let
us say that in all willing there is, first, a plurality of sensations, namely,
the sensation of the state "away
from which" [von dem weg],
the sensation of the state "towards
which," [zu dem hin] the
sensation of this "from"
and "towards"
themselves."(JGB § 19) The world is, before anything, given to us through
relation and affection, the world is effected through our human existence that
acts in the world and through the world. Nietzsche conceives of the will to
power, therefore, as the pathos of
personification, of incorporation, defying the very opposition of
"active" and "passive." In the same text (JGB § 19),
Nietzsche adds the interpretative aspect of the will to power, and besides the
complex of this feeling and thinking, the "affect of command" that
unveils the self-reflective character of the will to power. Action is never an
end in itself, but the means for the self-experience of agency through the
incorporation (Einverleibung) and
appropriation (Aneignung) of experiential,
interpretative worlds. Hence the resulting historicity of human practices: the
subject is always an historical effect, without presupposing determinism or
teleology --"necessity is not a fact but an interpretation."(WM §
552). Acting is always already temporal,
historicizing, insofar as it is effective (wirklich)
and not originally efficient (in the Aristotelian sense of causality). If
modern metaphysics relates every cause to the third --in the Aristotelian
classification of the four causes--, reducing thus the effect to a fact, the
Nietzschean transvaluation seeks to rescue the effectivity of the fact in a
radical critique that is regarded above all as interpretation.
We arrive thus at the
anthropological problem, displaced by the effective history of metaphysics,
after the unmasking of the great philosophies that disguised the human
phenomenon. As Plato by the mouth of Socrates approached the problem of genre (genos) to classify in logical fashion
what distinguishes the sophist from the philosopher, and what is just and true,
so Nietzsche resorts to a classifying method, without however, arriving at any
particular paradigm of classification. The Platonic idea of the Good, according
to Nietzsche's reading of metaphysics, would be subsequently disguised as final
cause in Aristotle, substance in Descartes, or thing-in-itself in Kant, without
ever succeeding in explaining what unites and opposes by analogy human beings
vis-à-vis all other beings. Hence the Socratic aporia of knowing that one knows
nothing, for the will to know always betrays the belief that there must be
meaning for all this endless network of signifiers. Man cannot constitute a
superior class, nor his reason a class of classes. All we are left with is the
fictionality of our human interpretations. Nietzsche uses thus typologies and
comparative observations on peoples, races, and nations of Antiquity, the
Renaissance, and Modernity not only to illustrate his doctrine of the will to
power but also to account for its historical, immanent grounds, proper to the
becoming of the human species. The very imposition of character of being to
becoming constitutes, according to Nietzsche, the supreme will to power.(WM §
617) But the character of being is not, as one might expect, stability and permanence;
on contrary, "that everything recurs
is the closest approximation of a world
of becoming to a world of being."(WM § 617) In this consists the amor fati (WM 1041, EH II,10), the
Dionysian self-affirmation of man that wills all his/her life and the whole
world happening exactly as it did happen --the eternal return of the same.
"The destination of human nature resides," as runs the Heraclitean
fragment, "in its character" --and vice-versa, ηθoς
αvθρωπω δαιμωv (Frag.
119).
5. Conclusion: The Critique of Modernity
Critique of modern man (his moralistic
mendaciousness): --the "good man" corrupted and seduced by bad
institutions (tyrants and priests); --reason as authority; --history as overcoming
of errors; --the future as progress; --the Christian state ("the Lord of
hosts");--the Christian sex impulse (or marriage); --the kingdom of
"justice" (the cult of "humanity");--"freedom"(WM
§ 62) That the man to be overcome is
"modern man" can be inferred from the incisive association between
the Übermensch and the Zukunft, the future, the Nietzschean
yet-to-come of the becoming. On the other hand, the concept of modernity
remains problematic in the study of Nietzsche's thought, insofar as it only
serves to envision radical projects --whether futurist or anarchist, nihilist
or post-modernist. It is indeed unwarranted, if not impossible, to reconcile
Kant's ethics with Nietzsche's radical critique of morals, as shown by the
studies by Mark Warren (post-modern political philosophy) and William Connolly
(radical liberalism).[24]
It was not the intent of the present work to examine the political, social
implications of Nietzsche's philosophy and his conception of modern man. All I
tried to show is that Nietzsche's genealogy is a continuation of the critical
project of modernity, although it breaks away from the philosophical
presuppositions of the Aufklärung, by
radicalizing and suspecting its conceptions of rationality and critique. The
rupture with "modernity" may be understood as the inauguration of
"post-modernity," but its ethical and political implications remain
to be seen. Foucault's contention, in the inaugural address at the Collège de
France, that the main difference between genealogy and critique is perspectival
and strategic rather than objective or thematic, bring us back to the questions
of method that have guided us in our inquiry into the nature of the modern
ethos.
Genealogy and critique, truth and
method, art and science, meaning and valor, ontology and semiology --these are
some of the fundamental concepts in Nietzsche's philosophy that proved useful
in the formulation of his anthropological problematic. To grasp the Nietzschean
"genealogy" as a radical "critique" that defies the metaphysical
method adopted by the Kantian Kritik
in philosophical and historical terms constitutes not only a thesis but also
the prelude to a project that articulates the genealogical discourse of
modernity. The anarchic, immoral anti-humanism and the anti-democratic
aristocracy generally associated with Nietzsche's name--even if we discount
here all the unwarranted speculations about an anti-semitic protofascism[25]--,
may easily mislead us to the conclusion that the Nietzsche's aestheticism had
nothing to contribute to a debate on human nature, let alone to ethics and
politics. Nevertheless, it is precisely
in this mined field of misunderstandings that we can redirect the Nietzschean
critique in a "post-metaphysical" sense that does justice to its
original project of the transvaluation of all values through the
self-overcoming of human nature. The critique of religion that culminates with
the death of God translates, in effect, the historical irreversibility of human
advancements in her/his constant search of herself/himself and the meaning of
existence, without any resort to grounds that transcend her/him. The
impossibility of founding the meaning of existence outside of the human
jurisdiction, beyond her/his historical experiences, is what makes Nietzsche's
philosophy the paradigm of our modern condition. To be sure, thinkers such as
Kant, Hegel and Feuerbach had already unmasked metaphysical conceptions of
human nature. The greatest difference between Nietzsche and these philosophers
is that he questions the very possibility of formulating a conception of human
nature, insofar as there have been and will always be some subjective,
power-effected interest behind every search for identity. Whoever asks
questions or lies behind them takes part in the codification of moral truths,
always bound to power relations. Nietzsche has shown that all philosophical
discourses of modernity have to presuppose, in their cultural, historical
articulation of ethics and politics, a metaphysics of subjectivity. Nietzsche
has thus undermined both the supra-historical and the metaphysical standpoints
that have allowed for modern historicism and criticism to proclaim the autonomy
of human freedom and reason. It is a matter of rescuing philosophy rather than
saving humankind. Hence the philosophical discourse of modernity must unveil
its nonphilosophical, lowly genesis, where the very creation of modern man is
effected by the will to truth and the will to power. In Beyond Good and Evil --particularly, in chapters 6 through 9 -- we
find out that, besides all the anthropological, psychological, and genealogical
analyses --undertaken in chapters 1 through 5--, there is indeed what we may
call an "ethnological" dimension to Nietzsche's. To be sure, the word
"ethnology" cannot be taken here in the modern sense "cultural
anthropology," of a science that studies, from a cultural standpoint,
so-called "primitive peoples" and compares them with the social,
historical formations of the great Oriental, Mesopotamic, and European civilizations.
In fact, as much can be said about anthropology and psychology in Nietzsche, in
that they remain on the boundary between the philosophical and the
nonphilosophical, as they seek to elucidate our knowledge of human nature
without reference to any specific empirical science (Fachwissenschaft). Therefore, the Nietzschean discourse on races,
civilizations, and cultural values can be examined within the philosophical
perspective that characterizes his cultural, historical background of late Aufklärung. On the other hand, the
originality of Nietzsche's project not only resists the previous
classifications of what had been then formulated as anthropology, psychology,
and genealogy, but questions all the scientific aspirations of these doctrines
that never dissimulated their essentially metaphysical foundations. It is
precisely in his antimetaphysical démarche
that Nietzsche can be considered one of the great precursors of contemporary
studies in cultural anthropology, inasmuch as it touches upon the social,
historical articulations of civilizing processes with the problem of otherness.[26]
It must be noted in passing that the problem of the cultural identity of a
given tribe, nation, or people, whatever constitutes them as an ethnos or genos to be differentiated from others, cannot be thought without
referring us back to a certain genealogical analysis of the moral, cultural
values (ethos) that bind them
together as a social group. It is in this articulation of historicity and
sociability within one single discourse that resides, in the last analysis,
Nietzsche's original contribution to a nonmetaphysical conception of human
nature, understood as the indeterminate, plastic becoming constituted by the
will to power, in its ontological regionalities and rationalities of
self-overcoming. The source of such a discourse is found, as we have seen, in
Nietzsche's conception of active and reactive forces at play in the historical
effectiveness of the will to power. The ethnological task outlined in JGB can
be also elucidated in function of the key concept of the will to power, as
opposed to modernist formulations of anthropology.
Just as the Kantian project --and
the philosophy of the Aufklärung in
general-- has been fairly characterized by an anthropocentric preoccupation,
Nietzsche outlined the true "critique of modern man" (WM § 62, quoted
above) and completed it with a "genealogy of modern man." For
Nietzsche, however, it is a matter of examining "modernity in the
perspective of the metaphor of nourishment and digestion"(WM § 71), i.e.,
the culture of fast food --Nietzsche
speaks of "time of influx prestissimo"!--,
the incapacity to digest, ruminate, meditate, and even think, that
characterizes the decadent man of a modernity that totally lost the Renaissance
sense of virtù and authenticity (WM
§§ 74-78). In a nutshell, the advent of the reactive, pessimist nihilism that
characterizes our modernity of fin of
siècle --as Nietzsche's Zeitgeist--,
only can be overcome in the becoming of its taking place (geschehen), interpreted and transvalued in active fashion. Thus,
what has become a code of conduct and truth for one epoch can be decodified in
the sense of a radical reversal of values, without losses or gains, but in the
simple preservation of quanta of forces. For instance, the codification of
morals and whatever is assimilated into the culture of a people, is always
accompanied by decodifications, hence the interpenetration of the Apollinian
and Dyonisian principles in the cultural formation of peoples and nations. To
the cultural ethos of a people, to
their mores structured by habituation
and socialization, correspond instincts of self-preservation, self-affirmation
as species, genos that generates and
reproduces itself in the genesis of a common destiny. It would be, therefore,
important to separate, in our reading of Nietzsche and, in particular, in our
reading of a genealogical critique, what is relevant to our understanding of a
Nietzschean interpretative principle from whatever refers to his
idiosyncrasies, in a peculiar context of fin
de siècle
I have to conclude this chapter in
provisional terms, as I am confined to elaborating on Nietzsche's contribution
to the problem of human nature. As Deleuze and Guattari observed, Nietzsche's
lasting contribution to the ethnological debate consists in the formulation of
a fundamental problem of primitive socius
in terms of code, inscription, trace: society is inscription-based rather than
exchange-based, the trace (on the body, on earth) is what defines culture in
its relations of contract and debt.[27]
If Kant was the first to have formulated the anthropological problem in a
pragmatic perspective --where abound the
idiosyncrasies and stereotypical views on gender, sex, ethnicity and social
divisions-- Nietzsche had the merits of suspecting and problematizing the
Kantian distinction between morals --that can be historically and socially
reconstituted-- and the moral law that makes possible, out of a transcendental
foundation, the moral actions of human beings. On the other hand, Nietzsche did
not seek to reconcile the universal and the particular in one single
anthropogenesis, nor did he content himself with a mere reversal of a
theological model --as Feuerbach did, in his conception of man as Gattungswesen. Nietzsche does not
provide us with a social theory, not even a theory of power that may help us
reformulate a social critique. His legacy is an aphoristic collection of
problems that enjoins us to revise and rethink our methods of classification
and representations of whom we claim to be, at an age of uncertainty and false
expectations.
E N D N O T E S
* . Originally published as Chapter 3 of On the Genealogy of Modernity: Foucault’s Social Philosophy. Hauppauge, NY: Nova Science, 2003.
[1].. M. Heidegger. Nietzsche, vol. 1,
[2].. Cf. Bernard Bueb, Nietzsches Kritik der praktischen
Vernunft, (Stuttgart: Ernst Klett, 1970); Siegfried Kittman, Kant und
Nietzsche: Darstellung und Vergleich ihrer Ethik und Moral, (Frankfurt am Main:
Peter Lang Verlag, 1984); Olivier Reboul, Nietzsche critique de Kant, (Paris:
PUF, 1978); Keith Ansell-Pearson, "Nietzsche's Overcoming of Kant and
Metaphysics: From Tragedy to Nihilism," Nietzsche-Studien 16 (1987)
310-339.
[3].. According to the Kröners Taschen edition (vol. 78,
1930); I am using the ET by Walter Kaufmann, The Will to Power, (New York:
Vintage Books, 1968).
[4].. Subtitle of the original outline for Hegel's
Phänomenologie des Geistes.
[5].. That is, that man is the only animal endowed with
the logos (speech, discourse, reason) and the zoon politikon by nature. Cf.
Aristotle's Politics I.i.
[6].. The years refer to the date of publication.
Undoubtedly, WM cannot be regarded as a "book" in the same sense as
AC and EH are regarded as "nachgelassene Werke". In the present
study, I have avoided both extreme positions of either discarding WM as a work
rejected by Nietzsche himself (as proposed by Bernd Magnus) or turning it into
the Hauptwerk containing the quintessential philosophy of Nietzsche (as
Heidegger does).
[7].. Cf. F. Nietzsche, "Le Philosophe. Considérations
sur le conflit de l'art et de la connaissance," in La naissance de la
philosophie à l'époque de la tragédie grecque, (Paris: Gallimard, 1985), 194.
[8].. 3rd. revised, augmented ed.,(New York: Vintage
Books, 1968). Some of Kaufmann's comments and editorial remarks were simply
outrageous --e.g., Nietzsche's notes on women and race.
[9].. To be sure, there were other philosophers who had
previously dealt with the problems of meaning and value, without however the
modern interest in critically submitting such formulations to a self-criticism
of the very method employed. Cf. G. Deleuze, Nietzsche et la philosophie,
(Paris: PUF, 1962), 1: "Le projet le plus général de Nietzsche consiste en
ceci: introduire en philosophie les concepts de sens et de valeur. Il est
évident que la philosophie moderne, en grande partie, a vécu et vit encore de
Nietzsche...Nietzsche n'a jamais caché que la philosophie du sens et des
valeurs dût être une critique. Que Kant n'a pas mené la vraie critique, parce
qu'il n'a pas su en poser le problème en termes de valeurs, tel est même un des
mobiles principaux de l'oeuvre de Nietzsche."
[10].. Cf. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method [Wahrheit
und Methode, 1st. ed. 1960; 2nd. ed. 1965], (New York: Crossroad, 1986), p.
495. The debate between Gadamer and Habermas, moderated by Paul Ricoeur
(Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences, ed. J.B. Thompson, Cambridge University
Press, 1981), may to a large extent be regarded as anticipating the
Foucault/Habermas "debate."
[11].. Cf. A. Megill, Prophets of Extremity: Nietzsche,
Heidegger, Foucault, Derrida, (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985),
2.
[12].. J. Derrida, "La mythologie blanche: La
métaphore dans le texte philosophique", in Marges de la philosophie,
[13].. In Kröner's edition, vol. 83, §§1208-1415.
[14].. M. Heidegger, "The Word of Nietzsche: 'God is
Dead'" [Nietzsches Wort "Gott ist tot", 1943] in The Question
Concerning Technology and Other Essays, tr. W. Lovitt, (New York: Harper &
Row, 1977), p. 54. Heidegger's reading of Nietzsche, insofar as historicity,
metaphysics, and nihilism are concerned, has been also elaborated in the essay
"Zur Seinsfrage", on the "line" of completion for the
fulfilling (Vollendung) of nihilism, in response to Ernst Jünger's essay,
"Über die Linie," in Wegmarken, (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1967).
[15].. Cf. M. Foucault, Folie et déraison: Histoire de la
folie à l'âge classique (Paris: Plon, 1961; 2e. ed. Gallimard,
1972); "Nietzsche, Freud, Marx" in Cahiers de Royaumont No.
VI, VIIe. Colloque, (4-8 juillet 1964), Paris: Minuit, 1967, pp.
183-200. When he was inquired whether Nietzsche underwent the experience of
madness ("que de grands esprits comme Nietzsche puissent avoir
l'expérience de la folie"), Foucault replied with a double yea, "oui,
oui!"
[16].. Cf. M. Heidegger, "The Word of Nietzsche: 'God
is Dead'", op. cit., 111-112; id., "Who is Nietzsche's
Zarathustra?", in David B. Allison (ed.), The New Nietzsche, op. cit.,
64-79.
[17].. In fact, Heidegger himself problematizes the
question of the overcoming (Überwindung) of metaphysics in terms of a
Verwindung (verwinden, venir à bout de, to cope with), esp. in the essay
"Zur Seinsfrage", op. cit. Cf. supra.
[18].. Such is in effect the great post-structuralist
thesis --and even anti-structuralist-- that Foucault would oppose to the
Heideggerian reading of Nietzsche and its fundamental-ontological appropriation
of the genealogy.
[19].. Cf. Excursus Two infra.
[20].. Cf. Jacques Derrida's critique of the Hegelian conception
of the concept in Glas, (Paris: Galilée, 1974).
[21].. FW Prelude §63:
"Called a star's orbit to pursue,/ What is the darkness, star, to you?/
Roll on in bliss, traverse this age--/ Its misery far from you and strange./
Let farthest world your light secure./ Pity is sin you must abjure./ But one
command is yours: be pure!" (Kaufmann' trans.)
[22].. Such are the readings of Heidegger, Nietzsche, op.
cit., vol. 1, The Will to Power as Art, and Lukács,The Destruction of Reason.
[23].. Cf. I. Kant, On History, ed. Lewis White Beck, (New
York: Macmillan, 1973).
[24].. Mark Warren, Nietzsche and Political Thought
(Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988); William Connolly, Political Theory and
Modernity (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1988).
[25].. Esp. Nietzsche's relationship with Wagner and the
speculations about his sister, Elisabeth, married to the leader of an
anti-Semitic, German movement, Bernhard Förster. Cf. Walter Kaufmann,
Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist, 3rd. edition, (New York:
Vintage, 1968); Jacques Derrida, The Ear of the Other, (Lincoln and London:
University of Nebraska Press, 1985).
[26].. Cf. Tzevan Todorov, Nous et les autres, (Paris:
Seuil, 1989).
[27].. Cf. 2nd.
essay of the GM; Anti-Oedipus, trans. R. Hurley, M. Seem and
Pós-modernidade para otários (PostModernity for dummies)
NIETZSCHE
NIETZSCHE & FOUCAULT
FOUCAULT