Vague Simples
Neil McKinnon
Abstract: Gareth Evans has argued influentially
against vague identities. David Lewis
and Theodore Sider have argued against vague parthood. Much of the distaste among philosophers for
metaphysical vagueness is sourced in these arguments. I argue that even if the considerations adduced by Evans, Lewis
and Sider are conclusive, metaphysical boundary vagueness remains possible.
1. Background
Here is a simplified account of Gareth
Evans' influential argument against metaphysical vagueness (1978). Suppose we
have a putative vague object, such as the Dead Sea. There are various precise
objects, differing only slightly at their peripheries, that we might describe
as being equally good candidates to be identical to the Dead Sea. Yet, from the
assumption that the Dead Sea is a vague object we can derive a contradiction.
If the Dead Sea is really a vague object then it is indeterminately identical
to each of the precise candidates. But this cannot be the case. Consider one of
the candidates, a. Although a is indeterminately identical to the
Dead Sea, it is determinately identical to a. However, the Dead Sea is
not determinately identical to a. The Dead Sea and a therefore
differ with respect to the property of being identical to a. And thus,
by the Indiscernibility of Identicals, we can infer that the Dead Sea is not
identical to a.
Timothy Williamson, though not ultimately sympathetic
to metaphysical vagueness, suggests that even if this argument is correct, it
does not follow that there is no metaphysical vagueness:
…[F]uzzy boundaries do not in any obvious
way require vague identity. Objects are
identical only if their boundaries have exactly the same fuzziness (Williamson,
1994, p. 255).
Along these lines, one obvious response to
Evans’ argument is to suggest that vagueness is located not in identity, but in
parthood; parthood, but not identity, is vague (ibid., p. 256). On this view,
there are xs for which it is indeterminate whether they are parts of the
Dead Sea, but the Dead Sea is not indeterminately identical to anything.
There are, however, objections to vague
parthood. If parthood is vague, then so
is composition. If the Dead Sea has
indeterminate parts, then there are pluralities of xs such that it is
indeterminate whether they compose the Dead Sea. And perhaps, composition cannot be vague. As Lewis puts it:
The question whether composition takes
place in a given case, whether a given class does or does not have a
mereological sum, can be stated in a part of language where nothing is vague.
Therefore it cannot have a vague answer (Lewis, 1986, p. 213).
Theodore Sider develops this argument by
noting that if composition were vague, it would be indeterminate how many
concrete objects exist. And since the
question, ‘How many concrete objects exist?’ can be expressed in non-vague
language, it must have a non-vague answer (Sider, 1997, pp. 221-22), contrary
to what we would expect if composition were vague. Another worry about vague
composition might flow from concerns that composition and identity are so
tightly connected that indeterminate composition entails indeterminate
identity. So Evans’ argument still has
purchase.
I will not attempt to adjudicate any of
these issues here. Instead, I will argue, even if we concede that there could
not be vague identities (as opposed to vague identity statements), nor
vagueness of composition, objects could nevertheless have vague boundaries.
2. Simples
Suppose that the world contains
mereological simples; objects with no proper parts. Suppose, also, that these objects are not point-particles, but
have spatial extension. The idea is
that these simples could still have vague boundaries. Consider such a simple.
There are spatial points and regions such that the simple is
determinately located at those points and regions. Yet, there are also points and regions at which the simple is
indeterminately located.
It might be objected that without recourse
to vague parthood there is no good reason to say that the simple is
determinately located at various points and regions but indeterminately located
at others. Simples lack the structure required to ground such differences. However,
I think no one who accepts that mereological simples could be spatially
extended ought to find this argument congenial, since a closely analogous
argument can be given to suggest that mereological simples could not have
spatial extension. Moreover, as I will
now urge, such arguments are mistaken.
Here is the analogous argument against
spatially extended simples. If an object has spatial extension then it has a
shape. An object's having spatial extension is consistent with its having all
sorts of shapes. We can explain why different objects have different shapes if
the objects have proper parts; the differing shapes are due to the different
configurations of each object's proper parts. But differing shapes among
simples cannot be accounted for in this way. Whatever shape a simple has, it
has as a matter of brute fact. And this is unacceptable.
Should we find this argument persuasive?
It would certainly be more than odd to say that objects with spatial proper
parts have their shapes as a matter of brute fact. But I see no non-question-begging reason for denying that
mereological simples have their shape as a matter of brute fact. If this is
right, then the objector must say that the notion of brute shapes is blatantly
incoherent. And it isn't.[1],[2]
Just as there is no non-question-begging argument against brute shape, I
doubt that a non-question-begging argument against brute boundary indeterminacy
is available. If there were metaphysical boundary indeterminacy for
mereologically complex objects, this indeterminacy would have to be accounted
for in terms of vague composition.[3]
But it is question-begging to draw conclusions from this about the boundary
indeterminacy of extended simples.
Again, the objector needs to say that such boundary indeterminacy is
blatantly incoherent. And again, so it
seems to me, it isn't.
3. Conclusion
It remains controversial whether Evans has
succeeded in showing that there could not be vague identities. It is also contentious whether parthood
could be vague. However, even if the
notions of vague identities and vague parthood are incoherent, metaphysical
boundary vagueness is not entirely vanquished. It could be the case that there
are mereological simples with vague boundaries, and vague complexes composed of
those simples.[4]
References
Evans, Gareth (1978), “Can There Be Vague
Objects?”, Analysis, 38, p. 208.
Lewis, David, (1986), On the Plurality
of Worlds, (Oxford: Blackwell).
Markosian, Ned, (1998), “Simples”, Australasian
Journal of Philosophy, 76, pp. 213-228.
Sider, Theodore, (1997),
“Four-Dimensionalism”, Philosophical Review, 106, pp. 197-231.
Williamson, Timothy, (1994), Vagueness,
(London: Routledge).
[1] See also Markosian (1998, pp. 222-4) on this issue.
[2]
Note
that we can still talk about the parts of extended simples in a Pickwickian
sense. I won't go into this matter in great detail, but a first approximation
involves identifying a simple’s Pickwickian parts with the parts of the spatial
region it occupies. This is not
ultimately satisfactory, however, since it would mean that the simple loses and
gains parts merely by moving! We don't want Pickwickian parts to be quite so
Pickwickian. Something more along the right lines would be to consider the
simple as a frame of reference. We set
up a co-ordinate system which is isomorphic to the region of space that the
simple occupies and regard these co-ordinates and their sums as the Pickwickian
parts. For vague simples, we include
not only co-ordinates for determinate Pickwickian parts, but co-ordinates for
indeterminate ones also. Even if talk of indeterminate parthood is
illegitimate, talk of indeterminate Pickwickian parts is not, because such talk
implies nothing about the vagueness or otherwise of genuine mereological
composition.
[3]
Except where the complex objects
are complexes of simples exhibiting boundary indeterminacy.
[4] Thanks to Su Rogerson for comments.